Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. Counterfactual Dependence and Time’s Arrow.David Lewis - 1979 - Noûs 13 (4):455-476.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   756 citations  
  • Egalitarianism and equal availability of political influence.Harry Brighouse - 1996 - Journal of Political Philosophy 4 (2):118–141.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   41 citations  
  • The Power of Numbers: On Agential Power‐With‐Others Without Power‐Over‐Others.Arash Abizadeh - 2021 - Philosophy and Public Affairs 49 (3):290-318.
    It is widely thought that if one cannot effect outcomes without others’ assistance, then one has agential power to effect those outcomes only if one has power over those whose assistance one requires. The corollary is that someone who just happens to find herself amongst people who share her preferences and would be disposed to help effect her preferred outcomes, but over whom she has no power, is lucky, but not thereby more powerful. This view is false. It ignores the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Resources, power and systematic luck: A response to Barry.Keith Dowding - 2003 - Politics, Philosophy and Economics 2 (3):305-322.
    Brian Barry attacks the `resource account' of power providing a set of definitions through which power should be analysed. While there might be different, equally good, ways of defining power, I argue that the formulations provided by Dowding are superior to those of Barry as they produce fewer anomalies and provide a better foundation for empirical research. The article defends the resource account against Barry's criticisms and argues for the utility of the ideas of luck and `systematic luck'. Key Words: (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • A Recursive Measure of Voting Power with Partial Decisiveness or Efficacy.Arash Abizadeh - 2022 - Journal of Politics 84 (3):1652-1666.
    The current literature standardly conceives of voting power in terms of decisiveness: the ability to change the voting outcome by unilaterally changing one’s vote. I argue that this classic conception of voting power, which fails to account for partial decisiveness or efficacy, produces erroneous results because it saddles the concept of voting power with implausible microfoundations. This failure in the measure of voting power in turn reflects a philosophical mistake about the concept of social power in general: a failure to (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation