Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. The Language of Thought.Jerry A. Fodor - 1975 - Harvard University Press.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1652 citations  
  • The Myth of Pain.Valerie Gray Hardcastle - 1999 - MIT Press.
    or Browse over 3500 reviews in " by Valerie Hardcastle, Ph.D. " _Metapsychology_.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   59 citations  
  • Representations, Targets, and Attitudes.Robert Cummins - 1996 - MIT Press.
    "This is an important new Cummins work.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   160 citations  
  • The Engine of Reason, the Seat of the Soul: A Philosophical Journey Into the Brain.Paul M. Churchland - 1995 - MIT Press.
    For the uninitiated, there are two major tendencies in the modeling of human cognition. The older, tradtional school believes, in essence, that full human cognition can be modeled by dividing the world up into distinct entities -- called __symbol s__-- such as “dog”, “cat”, “run”, “bite”, “happy”, “tumbleweed”, and so on, and then manipulating this vast set of symbols by a very complex and very subtle set of rules. The opposing school claims that this system, while it might be good (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   164 citations  
  • Of Sensory Systems and the "Aboutness" of Mental States.Kathleen Akins - 1996 - Journal of Philosophy 93 (7):337-372.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   101 citations  
  • What is a theory of mental representation?Stephen Stich - 1992 - Mind 101 (402):243-61.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   70 citations  
  • Does Reid reject/refute the representational theory of mind?Robert Stecker - 1992 - Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 73 (2):174-184.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Words in the brain's language. PulvermÜ & Friedemann Ller - 1999 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 22 (2):253-279.
    If the cortex is an associative memory, strongly connected cell assemblies will form when neurons in different cortical areas are frequently active at the same time. The cortical distributions of these assemblies must be a consequence of where in the cortex correlated neuronal activity occurred during learning. An assembly can be considered a functional unit exhibiting activity states such as full activation (“ignition”) after appropriate sensory stimulation (possibly related to perception) and continuous reverberation of excitation within the assembly (a putative (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   86 citations  
  • Content, computation, and externalism.Christopher Peacocke - 1994 - Mind and Language 9 (3):227-264.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   31 citations  
  • Explanation and evaluation in cognitive science.Richard Montgomery - 1995 - Philosophy of Science 62 (2):261-82.
    With some regularity, cognitive scientists seem to introduce cognitive values into their explanations. After identifying examples of this practice, I sketch an account of psychological explanation that, under certain conditions, legitimizes value-laden cognitive explanations in which evaluative claims appear in the explanandum. I then present and discuss two applications of the proposed account in order to show its viability and explore its consequences.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Truth, rules, hoverflies, and the Kripke-Wittgenstein paradox.Ruth Garrett Millikan - 1990 - Philosophical Review 99 (3):323-53.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   81 citations  
  • A deductive argument for the representational theory of thinking.William G. Lycan - 1993 - Mind and Language 8 (3):404-22.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Descartes’s Legacy: Minds and Meaning in Early Modern Philosophy.David B. Hausman & Alan Hausman - 1997 - University of Toronto Press.
    The Hausmans wed an intentional theory of ideas with a modern information theoretic approach in a critical tour of some of the most important issues in the philosophy of mind and some of the most outstanding figures in early modern philosophy.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Whose Theory? Which Representations?John Haldane - 1993 - Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 74 (3):247-257.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • The architecture of representation.Rick Grush - 1997 - Philosophical Psychology 10 (1):5-23.
    b>: In this article I outline, apply, and defend a theory of natural representation. The main consequences of this theory are: i) representational status is a matter of how physical entities are used, and specifically is not a matter of causation, nomic relations with the intentional object, or information; ii) there are genuine (brain-)internal representations; iii) such representations are really representations, and not just farcical pseudo-representations, such as attractors, principal components, state-space partitions, or what-have-you;and iv) the theory allows us to (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   68 citations  
  • Representational parts.Rick Grush & Pete Mandik - 2002 - Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences 1 (4):389-394.
    In this reply we claim that, contra Dreyfus, the kinds of skillful performances Dreyfus discusses _are_ representational. We explain this proposal, and then defend it against an objection to the effect that the representational notion we invoke is a weak one countenancing only some global state of an organism as a representation. According to this objection, such a representation is not a robust, projectible property of an organism, and hence will gain no explana- tory leverage in cognitive scientific explanations. We (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Review of Cummins' Representations, Targets, and Attitudes. [REVIEW]Frances Egan - 1998 - Philosophical Review 107 (1):118.
    “Naturalistic” semantic theories attempt to specify, in nonintentional and nonsemantic terms, a sufficient condition for a mental representation’s having a particular meaning. Such theories have trouble accounting for the possibility of representational error. In his latest book, Robert Cummins traces the problem to the fact that the theories currently on offer identify the meaning of a representation with certain features of its use. Only a theory that takes meaning to be an intrinsic feature of a representation, Cummins argues, can both (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   24 citations  
  • Knowledge Representation and Metaphor.E. Cornell Way - 1991 - Springer Verlag.
    This series will include monographs and collections of studies devoted to the investigation and exploration of knowledge, information, and data processing systems of all kinds, no matter whether human, (other) animal, or machine. Its scope is intended to span the full range of interests from classical problems in the philosophy of mind and philosophical psychol ogy through issues in cognitive psychology and sociobiology (concerning the mental capabilities of other species) to ideas related to artificial intelligence and computer science. While primary (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   21 citations  
  • The Science of the Mind.Owen J. Flanagan - 1984 - MIT Press.
    Consciousness emerges as the key topic in this second edition of Owen Flanagan's popular introduction to cognitive science and the philosophy of psychology....
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   206 citations  
  • "Purple Haze: The Puzzle of Consciousness" by Joseph Levine, "Phenomenal Consciousness: A Naturalistic Theory" by Peter Carruthers, and "The Nature of Consciousness" by Mark Rowlands. [REVIEW]Tim Crane - 2002 - Times Literary Supplement 5176:9-10.
    The Vienna Circle was a group of scientifically-minded philosophers, many physicists by training, who in the 1920s and 30s developed the cluster of philosophical doctrines known as Logical Positivism. Among the Circle’s most distinguished members were Rudolf Carnap and Herbert Feigl, each of whom emigrated to America during the Nazi era. It is said that Feigl, the author of an important 1958 monograph defending a materialist approach to the mind-body problem, once gave a visiting lecture on the problem of consciousness (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation