Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. Self-constitution: agency, identity, and integrity.Christine M. Korsgaard - 2009 - New York: Oxford University Press.
    Agency and identity -- Necessitation -- Acts and actions -- Aristotle and Kant -- Agency and practical identity -- The metaphysics of normativity -- Constitutive standards -- The constitution of life -- In defense of teleology -- The paradox of self-constitution -- Formal and substantive principles of reason -- Formal versus substantive -- Testing versus weighing -- Maximizing and prudence -- Practical reason and the unity of the will -- The empiricist account of normativity -- The rationalist account of normativity (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   533 citations  
  • Creating the Kingdom of Ends.Christine M. Korsgaard - 1996 - New York, NY, USA: Cambridge University Press.
    Christine Korsgaard has become one of the leading interpreters of Kant's moral philosophy. She is identified with a small group of philosophers who are intent on producing a version of Kant's moral philosophy that is at once sensitive to its historical roots while revealing its particular relevance to contemporary problems. She rejects the traditional picture of Kant's ethics as a cold vision of the moral life which emphasises duty at the expense of love and value. Rather, Kant's work is seen (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   471 citations  
  • The constitution of agency: essays on practical reason and moral psychology.Christine M. Korsgaard - 2008 - New York: Oxford University Press.
    Christine M. Korsgaard is one of today's leading moral philosophers: this volume collects ten influential papers by her on practical reason and moral psychology ...
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   168 citations  
  • The Practice of Moral Judgment.Barbara Herman - 1985 - Journal of Philosophy 82 (8):414.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   346 citations  
  • The form of practical knowledge: a study of the categorical imperative.Stephen P. Engstrom - 2009 - Cambridge: Harvard University Press.
    Introduction -- Part I: Willing as practical knowing -- The will and practical judgment -- Fundamental practical judgments : the wish for happiness -- Part II: From presuppositions of judgment to the idea of a categorical imperative -- The formal presuppositions of practical judgment -- Constraints on willing -- Part III: Interpretation -- The categorical imperative -- Applications -- Conclusion.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   123 citations  
  • (1 other version)Lectures on the history of moral philosophy.John Rawls - 2000 - Cambridge: Harvard University Press. Edited by Barbara Herman.
    This book brings together the lectures that inspired a generation of students--and a regeneration of moral philosophy.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   149 citations  
  • (1 other version)Kant.Paul Guyer - 2006 - New York: Routledge.
    In this updated edition of his outstanding introduction to Kant, Paul Guyer uses Kant’s central conception of autonomy as the key to his thought. Beginning with a helpful overview of Kant’s life and times, Guyer introduces Kant’s metaphysics and epistemology, carefully explaining his arguments about the nature of space, time and experience in his most influential but difficult work, _The Critique of Pure Reason_. He offers an explanation and critique of Kant’s famous theory of transcendental idealism and shows how much (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   130 citations  
  • Kantian ethics almost without apology.Marcia Baron - 1995 - Ithaca: Cornell University Press.
    The emphasis on duly in Kant's ethics is widely held to constitute a defect. Marcia W. Baron develops and assesses the criticism, which she sees as comprising two objections: that duty plays too large a role, leaving no room for the supererogatory, and that Kant places too much value on acting from duty. Clearly written and cogently argued, Kantian Ethics Almost without Apology takes on the most philosophically intriguing objections to Kant's ethics and subjects them to a rigorous yet sympathetic (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   113 citations  
  • Moral literacy.Barbara Herman - 2007 - New York: Harvard University Press.
    Making room for character -- Pluralism and the community of moral judgment -- A cosmopolitan kingdom of ends --Responsibility and moral competence --Can virtue be taught?: the problem of new moral facts -- Training to autonomy: Kant and the question of moral education -- Bootstrapping -- Rethinking Kant's hedonism -- The scope of moral requirement -- The will and its objects -- Obligatory ends -- Moral improvisation -- Contingency in obligation.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   83 citations  
  • Kant.Allen W. Wood - 2004 - Malden, MA: Wiley-Blackwell.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   83 citations  
  • Kant.Henry E. Allison - 1995 - In Ted Honderich, The Philosophers: Introducing Great Western Thinkers. New York: Oxford University Press.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   129 citations  
  • Laws of freedom.Mary J. Gregor - 1963 - Oxford,: Blackwell.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   47 citations  
  • A Kant Dictionary.Howard Caygill (ed.) - 1995 - Wiley-Blackwell.
    In this new lexical survey of Kant's works, Howard Caygill presents Kantian concepts and terminology in terms that will introduce and clarify his ideas for students and general readers alike.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   47 citations  
  • Kant, Duty and Moral Worth.Philip Stratton-Lake - 2000 - New York: Routledge.
    _Kant, Duty and Moral Worth _is a fascinating and original examination of Kant's account of moral worth. The complex debate at the heart of Kant's philosophy is over whether Kant said moral actions have worth only if they are carried out from duty, or whether actions carried out from mixed motives can be good. Philip Stratton-Lake offers a unique account of acting from duty, which utilizes the distinction between primary and secondary motives. He maintains that the moral law should not (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   43 citations  
  • Kant on imperfect duty and supererogation.Thomas E. Hill Jr - 1971 - Kant Studien 62 (1-4):55-76.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   63 citations  
  • Acting on Principle: An Essay on Kantian Ethics.Onora O'Neill - 1975 - New York: Cambridge University Press.
    'Two things', wrote Kant, 'fill the mind with ever new and increasing admiration and awe: the starry heavens above and the moral law within'. Many would argue that since Kant's day, the study of the starry heavens has advanced while ethics has stagnated, and in particular that Kant's ethics offers an empty formalism that tells us nothing about how we should live. In Acting on Principle Onora O'Neill shows that Kantian ethics has practical as well as philosophical importance. First published (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   36 citations  
  • Self-constitution in the ethics of Plato and Kant.Christine M. Korsgaard - 1999 - The Journal of Ethics 3 (1):1-29.
    Plato and Kant advance a constitutional model of the soul, in which reason and appetite or passion have different structural and functional roles in the generation of motivation, as opposed to the familiar Combat Model in which they are portrayed as independent sources of motivation struggling for control. In terms of the constitutional model we may explain what makes an action different from an event. What makes an action attributable to a person, and therefore what makes it an action, is (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   56 citations  
  • Kantian Beneficence and the Problem of Obligatory Aid.Karen Stohr - 2011 - Journal of Moral Philosophy 8 (1):45-67.
    Common sense tells us that in certain circumstances, helping someone is morally obligatory. That intuition appears incompatible with Kant's account of beneficence as a wide imperfect duty, and its implication that agents may exercise latitude over which beneficent actions to perform. In this paper, I offer a resolution to the problem from which it follows that some opportunities to help admit latitude and others do not. I argue that beneficence has two components: the familiar wide duty to help others achieve (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   33 citations  
  • Kant's moral philosophy.Robert N. Johnson - 2008 - Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
    Immanuel Kant (1724–1804) argued that moral requirements are based on a standard of rationality he dubbed the “Categorical Imperative” (CI). Immorality thus involves a violation of the CI and is thereby irrational. Other philosophers, such as Locke and Hobbes, had also argued that moral requirements are based on standards of rationality. However, these standards were either desirebased instrumental principles of rationality or based on sui generis rational intuitions. Kant agreed with many of his predecessors that an analysis of practical reason (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   39 citations  
  • Kant, Ought Implies Can, the Principle of Alternate Possibilities, and Happiness.Samuel Kahn - 2018 - Lexington Books.
    This book examines three issues: the principle of ought implies can ; the principle of alternate possibilities ; and Kant’s views on the duty to promote one’s own happiness. It argues that although Kant was wrong to deny such a duty, the part of his denial that rests on a conception of duty incorporating both OIC and PAP is sound.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Kant.Patricia Kitcher, Philip Kitcher & Ralph C. S. Walker - 1980 - Philosophical Review 89 (2):282.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   55 citations  
  • Motivation, metaphysics, and the value of the self: A reply to Ginsborg, Guyer, and Schneewind.Christine Korsgaard - 1998 - Ethics 109 (1):49-66.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   34 citations  
  • Making room for character.Barbara Herman - 1996 - In Stephen Engstrom & Jennifer Whiting, Aristotle, Kant, and the Stoics: Rethinking Happiness and Duty. Cambridge University Press. pp. 36--60.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   34 citations  
  • Kantian Ethics, Animals, and the Law.Christine M. Korsgaard - 2013 - Oxford Journal of Legal Studies 33 (4):629-648.
    Legal systems divide the world into persons and property, treating animals as property. Some animal rights advocates have proposed treating animals as persons. Another option is to introduce a third normative category. This raises questions about how normative categories are established. In this article I argue that Kant established normative categories by determining what the presuppositions of rational practice are. According to Kant, rational choice presupposes that rational beings are ends in themselves and the rational use of the earth’s resources (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   21 citations  
  • Decision Procedures, Moral Criteria, and the Problem of Relevant Descriptions in Kant's Ethics.Mark Timmons - 1994 - In B. Sharon Byrd, Joachim Hruschka & Jan C. Joerdan, Jahrbuck fur Recht und Ethik (Annual for Law and Ethics). Duncker Und Humblot.
    I argue that the Universal Law formulation of the Categorical Imperative is best interpreted as a test or decision procedure of moral rightness and not as a criterion intended to explain the deontic status of actions. Rather, the Humanity formulation is best interpreted as a moral criterion. I also argue that because the role of a moral criterion is to explain, and thus specify what makes an action right or wrong, Kant's Humanity formulation yields a theory of relevant descriptions.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Kant and the Foundations of Morality.Halla Kim - 2014 - Lanham, Maryland: Lexington Books.
    Kim examines the fundamental tenets of Immanuel Kant’s theory of morality structural-methodological point of view to highlight the activities of reason vis-à-vis the blind forces of brute nature. The study provides new perspective on Kant's thought to benefit studies of epistemology, modern philosophy, moral theory and philosophy, and ethics.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • I. Kant after virtue.Onora O'Neill - 1983 - Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 26 (4):387 – 405.
    Maclntyre's refurbishing of Aristotelian ethics aims to restore both intelligibility and rationality to moral discourse. In After Virtue he concentrates on showing how intelligible action requires that lives be led within institutional and cultural traditions. But he does not offer a developed account of practical reason which could provide grounds for seeking some rather than other intelligible continuations of lives and traditions. Despite Maclntyre's criticisms of Kant's ethics, a Kantian account of practical reasoning may complement his account of intelligibility. An (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • What Is a Maxim?Patricia Kitcher - 2003 - Philosophical Topics 31 (1-2):215-243.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • Kant on Happiness and Reason.Alison Hills - 2006 - History of Philosophy Quarterly 23 (3):243 - 261.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Positive Duties, Maxim Realism and the Deliberative Field.Samuel Kahn - 2017 - Philosophical Inquiry 41 (4):2-34.
    My goal in this paper is to show that it is not the case that positive duties can be derived from Kant’s so-called universalizability tests. I begin by explaining in detail what I mean by this and distinguishing it from a few things that I am not doing in this paper. After that, I confront the idea of a maxim contradictory, a concept that is advanced by many com- mentators in the attempt to derive positive duties from the universalizability tests. (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • The principle of alternate possibilities and 'ought' implies 'can'.Ira M. Schnall - 2001 - Analysis 61 (4):335-340.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • The Categorical Imperative and Universalizability.Dieter Schönecker & Christoph Horn - 2006 - In Dieter Schönecker & Christoph Horn, Groundwork for the Metaphysics of Morals. Walter de Gruyter.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • (1 other version)More on "Ought" Implies "Can" and the Principle of Alternate Possibilities.Gideon Yaffe - 2005 - Midwest Studies in Philosophy 29 (1):307-312.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Impermissibility and Kantian Moral Worth.Jill Graper Hernandez - 2010 - Ethical Theory and Moral Practice 13 (4):403-419.
    Samuel Kerstein argues that an asymmetry between moral worth and maxims prevents Kant from accepting a category of acts that are impermissible, but have moral worth. Kerstein contends that an act performed from the motive of duty should be considered as a candidate for moral worth, even if the action's maxim turns out to be impermissible, since moral worth depends on the correct moral motivation of an act, rather than on the moral lightness of an act. I argue that Kant (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Happiness as a Natural End.Robert N. Johnson - 2002 - In Mark Timmons, Kant's Metaphysics of morals: interpetative essays. New York: Oxford University Press.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Kantian ethical duties.Faviola Rivera - 2006 - Kantian Review 11:78-101.
    Perfect ethical duties have usually puzzled commentators on Kant's ethics because they do not fit neatly within his taxonomy of duties. Ethical duties require the adoption of maxims of ends: the happiness of others and one's own perfection are Kant's two main categories. These duties, he claims, are of wide obligation because they do not specify what in particular one ought to do, when, and how much. They leave ‘a latitude for free choice’ as he puts it. Perfect duties, however, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • From the Forbidden to the Supererogatory: The Basic Ethical Categories in Kant's "Tugendlehre".Paul D. Eisenberg - 1966 - American Philosophical Quarterly 3 (4):255-269.
    Of the six basic categories which a normative ethical theory may recognize and exemplify, The first five are fairly clearly employed by kant in the "tugendlehre", But the sixth is not given adequate recognition by him. In order to establish those conclusions, One has to investigate the leading notion of the "tugendlehre", That of obligatory ends. Closely connected with that notion is kant's division of duties into perfect and imperfect ones. Consideration of a number of ways of elucidating that division (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations