Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. Aristotle and the Problem of Intentionality.Victor Caston - 1998 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 58 (2):249-298.
    Aristotle not only fonnulates the problem of intentionality explicitly, he makes a solution to it a requirement for any adequate theory of mind. His own solution, however, is not to be found in his theory of sensation, as Brentano and others have thought. In fact, it is precisely because Aristotle regards this theory as inadequate that he goes on to argue for a distinct new ability he calls “phantasia.” The theory of content he develops on this basis (unlike Brentano’s) is (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   38 citations  
  • Aristotle and the problem of intentionality.Victor Caston - 1998 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 58 (2):249-298.
    Aristotle not only formulates the problem of intentionality explicitly, he makes a solution to it a requirement for any adequate theory of mind. His own solution, however, is not to be found in his theory of sensation, as Brentano and others have thought. In fact, it is precisely because Aristotle regards this theory as inadequate that he goes on to argue for a distinct new ability he calls "phantasia." The theory of content he develops on this basis (unlike Brentano's) is (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   38 citations  
  • Why Aristotle Needs Imagination.Victor Caston - 1996 - Phronesis 41 (1):20-55.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   37 citations  
  • Aristotle, De Anima.Harald A. T. Reiche & David Ross - 1963 - American Journal of Philology 84 (2):205.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  • Aristotle on Common Perception.Laura Papish - 2014 - Apeiron 47 (3):342-55.
    In his account of human perception in De Anima, Aristotle focuses on characterizing special perception and its objects. This focus, however, comes at a price, as Aristotle neglects to explain why incidental and common objects should also be called objects of perception. My goal is to reconstruct on Aristotle’s behalf a plausible account of why the commons can rightly be called objects of perception.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • De Anima II 5.M. F. Burnyeat - 2002 - Phronesis 47 (1):28 - 90.
    This is a close scrutiny of "De Anima II 5", led by two questions. First, what can be learned from so long and intricate a discussion about the neglected problem of how to read an Aristotelian chapter? Second, what can the chapter, properly read, teach us about some widely debated issues in Aristotle's theory of perception? I argue that it refutes two claims defended by Martha Nussbaum, Hilary Putnam, and Richard Sorabji: (i) that when Aristotle speaks of the perceiver becoming (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   32 citations  
  • Aristotle: The Power of Perception.Tim Maudlin & Deborah K. W. Modrak - 1990 - Philosophical Review 99 (2):305.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   40 citations  
  • Aristotle and Alexander on Perceptual Error.Mark A. Johnstone - 2015 - Phronesis 60 (3):310-338.
    Aristotle sometimes claims that the perception of special perceptibles by their proper sense is unerring. This claim is striking, since it might seem that we quite often misperceive things like colours, sounds and smells. Aristotle also claims that the perception of common perceptibles is more prone to error than the perception of special perceptibles. This is puzzling in its own right, and also places constraints on the interpretation of. I argue that reading Alexander of Aphrodisias on perceptual error can help (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Aristotle De Anima.Wm A. Hammond & R. D. Hicks - 1909 - Philosophical Review 18 (2):234.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   37 citations  
  • Blind-Spots in Aristotle’s Doctrine of the Perceptual Mean.Roberto Grasso - 2020 - Apeiron 53 (3):257-284.
    This paper aims to identify several interpretive problems posed by the final part of DA II.11, where Aristotle intertwines the thesis that a sense is like a ‘mean’ and an explanation for the existence of a ‘blind spot’ related to the sense of touch, adding the further contention that we are capable of discriminating because the mean ‘becomes the other opposite’ in relation to the perceptible property being perceived. To solve those problems, the paper explores a novel interpretation of Aristotle’s (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Aristotle. On the Soul, Parva Naturalia, on Breath.Harold Cherniss & W. S. Hett - 1936 - American Journal of Philology 57 (2):228.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Aristotle's Account of Incidental Perception.Stanford Cashdollar - 1973 - Phronesis 18 (1):156-175.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  • De anima II 5.Myles F. Burnyeat - 2002 - Phronesis 47 (1):28-90.
    This is a close scrutiny of De Anima II 5, led by two questions. First, what can be learned from so long and intricate a discussion about the neglected problem of how to read an Aristotelian chapter? Second, what can the chapter, properly read, teach us about some widely debated issues in Aristotle's theory of perception? I argue that it refutes two claims defended by Martha Nussbaum, Hilary Putnam, and Richard Sorabji: that when Aristotle speaks of the perceiver becoming like (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   30 citations  
  • Truth and error in Aristotle's theory of sense perception.Irving Block - 1961 - Philosophical Quarterly 11 (42):1-9.
    Why does aristotle say that the common sensibles are susceptible to error while the specific sensibles are not? various solutions of this problem are discussed and finally it is concluded that aristotle's meaning here is teleological. The specific senses were fashioned by nature to perceive the specific sensibles but not the common sensibles and so error sometimes (often) creeps in. The common sense is really not a sense faculty as the eye, The ear etc.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  • Aristotle on the Intelligibility of Perception.Eve Rabinoff - 2015 - Review of Metaphysics 68 (4):719-740.
    This article addresses the question of how, by Aristotle’s lights, we apprehend concrete individuals, the objects of incidental perception. The author argues (a) that the incidental perceptible is indeed perceived and not interpreted, and (b) that what is perceived incidentally is an object as it bears significance to the projects and aims of the perceiver, rather than what the object is in itself (as it is commonly taken to be). Finally, the author argues (c) that this new way of understanding (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Aristotle’s Perceptual Optimism.Pavel Gregorić - 2019 - Croatian Journal of Philosophy 19 (3):543-560.
    In this paper, I would like to present Aristotle’s attitude to sense-perception. I will refer to this attitude as “perceptual optimism”. Perceptual optimism is, very briefly, the position that the senses give us full access to reality as it is. Perceptual optimism entails perceptual realism, the view that there is a reality out there which is accessible to our senses in some way or other, and the belief that our senses are veridical at least to some extent, but it is (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation