Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. Scientific Realism and the Plasticity of Mind.Paul M. Churchland (ed.) - 1979 - New York: Cambridge University Press.
    A study in the philosophy of science, proposing a strong form of the doctrine of scientific realism' and developing its implications for issues in the philosophy of mind.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   537 citations  
  • The Language of Thought.J. A. Fodor - 1978 - Critica 10 (28):140-143.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1463 citations  
  • (1 other version)Special sciences (or: The disunity of science as a working hypothesis).Jerry Fodor - 1974 - Synthese 28 (2):97-115.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   658 citations  
  • Unity of Science as a Working Hypothesis.Paul Oppenheim & Hilary Putnam - 1958 - Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science 2:3-36.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   365 citations  
  • Multiple Realizability Revisited: Linking Cognitive and Neural States.William Bechtel - 1999 - Philosophy of Science 66 (2):175-207.
    The claim of the multiple realizability of mental states by brain states has been a major feature of the dominant philosophy of mind of the late 20th century. The claim is usually motivated by evidence that mental states are multiply realized, both within humans and between humans and other species. We challenge this contention by focusing on how neuroscientists differentiate brain areas. The fact that they rely centrally on psychological measures in mapping the brain and do so in a comparative (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   199 citations  
  • Representations: Philosophical Essays on the Foundations of Cognitive Science.Jerry A. Fodor - 1983 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 34 (2):175-182.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   192 citations  
  • (1 other version)Simple Minds.Jean R. Kazez & Dan Lloyd - 1994 - Philosophical Review 103 (4):718.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   146 citations  
  • Why not the whole iguana?Daniel C. Dennett - 1978 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 1 (1):103-104.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   91 citations  
  • Cognition in the Wild.Edward Hutchins - 1995 - Critica 27 (81):101-105.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   784 citations  
  • Nonreductive materialism and the explanatory autonomy of psychology.Terence E. Horgan - 1993 - In Steven J. Wagner & Richard Wagner (eds.), Naturalism: A Critical Appraisal. University of Notre Dame Press.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   43 citations  
  • Philosophical Papers.Michael Friedman & Hilary Putnam - 1977 - Philosophical Review 86 (4):545.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   54 citations  
  • Towards a General Theory of Reduction. Part III: Cross-Categorical Reduction.C. A. Hooker - 1981 - Dialogue 20 (3):496-529.
    Any theory of reduction that goes only so far as carried in Parts I and II does only half the job. Prima facie at least, there are cases of would-be reduction which seem torn between two conflicting intuitions. On the one side there is a strong intuition that reduction is involved, and a strongly retentive reduction at that. On the other side it seems that the concepts at one level cross-classify those at the other level, so that there is no (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   29 citations  
  • (2 other versions)What is it like to be boring and myopic?Kathleen Akins - 1993 - In Bo Dahlbom (ed.), Dennett and His Critics. Cambridge, Mass., USA: Wiley-Blackwell.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   26 citations  
  • Levels of explanation.David Owens - 1989 - Mind 98 (389):59-79.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   22 citations  
  • Neural constraints in cognitive science.Keith Butler - 1994 - Minds and Machines 4 (2):129-62.
    The paper is an examination of the ways and extent to which neuroscience places constraints on cognitive science. In Part I, I clarify the issue, as well as the notion of levels in cognitive inquiry. I then present and address, in Part II, two arguments designed to show that facts from neuroscience are at a level too low to constrain cognitive theory in any important sense. I argue, to the contrary, that there are several respects in which facts from neurophysiology (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Neuroethology and the philosophy of cognitive science.Brian L. Keeley - 2000 - Philosophy of Science 67 (S1):404-418.
    Neuroethology is a branch of biology that studies the neural basis of naturally occurring animal behavior. This science, particularly a recent program called computational neuroethology, has a similar structure to the interdisciplinary endeavor of cognitive science. I argue that it would be fruitful to conceive of cognitive science as the computational neuroethology of humans. However, there are important differences between the two sciences, including the fact that neuroethology is much more comparative in its perspective. Neuroethology is a biological science and (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • The Problem of Simple Minds: Is There Anything It Is Like to Be a Honey Bee? [REVIEW]Michael Tye - 1997 - Philosophical Studies 88 (3):289-317.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   27 citations  
  • Fixing content and function in neurobiological systems: The neuroethology of electroreception. [REVIEW]Brian L. Keeley - 1999 - Biology and Philosophy 14 (3):395-430.
    Are attributions of content and function determinate, or is there no fact of the matter to be fixed? Daniel Dennett has argued in favor of indeterminacy and concludes that, in practice, content and function cannot be fixed. The discovery of an electrical modality in vertebrates offers one concrete instance where attributions of function and content are supported by a strong scientific consensus. A century ago, electroreception was unimagined, whereas today it is widely believed that many species of bony fish, amphibians, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations