Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. What is a (social) structural explanation?Sally Haslanger - 2016 - Philosophical Studies 173 (1):113-130.
    A philosophically useful account of social structure must accommodate the fact that social structures play an important role in structural explanation. But what is a structural explanation? How do structural explanations function in the social sciences? This paper offers a way of thinking about structural explanation and sketches an account of social structure that connects social structures with structural explanation.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   143 citations  
  • Ontology and Social Construction.Sally Haslanger - 1995 - Philosophical Topics 23 (2):95-125.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   98 citations  
  • What is Objectification?Lina Papadaki - 2010 - Journal of Moral Philosophy 7 (1):16-36.
    Objectification is a notion central to contemporary feminist theory. It has famously been associated with the work of anti-pornography feminists Catharine MacKinnon and Andrea Dworkin, and more recently with the work of Martha Nussbaum. However, objectification is a notion that has not yet been adequately defined. It has been used rather vaguely to refer to a broad range of cases involving, in some way or another, the treatment of a person as an object. My purpose in this paper is to (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  • The ethics of sexual objectification: Autonomy and consent.Patricia Marino - 2008 - Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 51 (4):345 – 364.
    It is now a platitude that sexual objectification is wrong. As is often pointed out, however, some objectification seems morally permissible and even quite appealing—as when lovers are so inflamed by passion that they temporarily fail to attend to the complexity and humanity of their partners. Some, such as Nussbaum, have argued that what renders objectification benign is the right sort of relationship between the participants; symmetry, mutuality, and intimacy render objectification less troubling. On this line of thought, pornography, prostitution, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Karl Marx.Jonathan Wolff - 2008 - Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
    Karl Marx (1818-1883) is best known not as a philosopher but as a revolutionary communist, whose works inspired the foundation of many communist regimes in the twentieth century. It is hard to think of many who have had as much influence in the creation of the modern world. Trained as a philosopher, Marx turned away from philosophy in his mid-twenties, towards economics and politics. However, in addition to his overtly philosophical early work, his later writings have many points of contact (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • The labor theory of value and the concept of exploitation.G. A. Cohen - 1979 - Philosophy and Public Affairs 8 (4):338-360.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   37 citations  
  • Objectification.Martha C. Nussbaum - 1995 - Philosophy and Public Affairs 24 (4):249-291.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   166 citations  
  • Sexual Objectification.K. Stock - 2015 - Analysis 75 (2):191-195.
    Sexual objectification, in the broadest terms, involves treating people as things. Philosophers have offered different accounts of what, more precisely, this involves. According to the conjoint view of Catherine Mackinnon and Sally Haslanger, sexual objectification is necessarily morally objectionable. According to Martha Nussbaum, it is not: there can be benign instances of it, in the course of a healthy sexual relationship, for instance. This is taken to be a serious disagreement, both by Nussbaum and by recent commentators such as Lina (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Desire.Tim Schroeder - 2006 - Philosophy Compass 1 (6):631–639.
    Desires move us to action, give us urges, incline us to joy at their satisfaction, and incline us to sorrow at their frustration. Naturalistic work on desire has focused on distinguishing which of these phenomena are part of the nature of desire, and which are merely normal consequences of desiring. Three main answers have been proposed. The first holds that the central necessary fact about desires is that they lead to action. The second makes pleasure the essence of desire. And (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   49 citations  
  • On being objective and being objectified.S. Haslanger - 1993 - In L. Antony (ed.), A Mind of One's Own. Westview. pp. 209--53.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   53 citations  
  • Feminism.Clare Chambers - 2013 - In Michael Freeden, Lyman Tower Sargent & Marc Stears (eds.), The Oxford Handbook of Political Ideologies. Oxford University Press. pp. 562-582.
    This chapter sets out the state of contemporary feminism, including considering the sense in which it is and is not an ideology. It argues that contemporary feminism must argue against two patriarchal claims: The Prison of Biology and The Fetishism of Choice. In their place, feminism argues for three theses: The Entrenchment of Gender, The Existence of Patriarchy, and The Need for Change.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Alienation: The Concept and Its Reception. [REVIEW][author unknown] - 1991 - Review of Metaphysics 44 (3):651-653.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   66 citations