Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. Aristotle on Other-Selfhood and Reciprocal Shaping.Anthony Carreras - 2012 - History of Philosophy Quarterly 29 (4):319-336.
    This paper concerns the status of Aristotle’s claim that a friend is another self in NE IX.4. Against the prevailing interpretation, I defend the view that Aristotle uses the other-self claim to explain how a virtuous person who values himself will come to value his friend, according to which 1) loving a friend is an extension of self-love, and 2) the conception of the friend as another self explains how the friend’s eudaimonia becomes constitutive of the agent’s eudaimonia. I argue (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Impersonal Friends.Jennifer E. Whiting - 1991 - The Monist 74 (1):3-29.
    The rationality of concern for oneself has been taken for granted by the authors of western moral and political thought in a way in which the rationality of concern for others has not. While various authors have differed about the morality of self-concern, and about the extent to which such concern is rationally required, few have doubted that we have at least some special reasons to care for our selves, reasons that differ either in degree or in kind from those (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   38 citations  
  • Self-love in Aristotle.Julia Annas - 1989 - Southern Journal of Philosophy 27 (S1):1-18.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   23 citations  
  • Aristotle's ethics.David Bostock - 2000 - New York: Oxford University Press.
    In this fascinating introduction, David Bostock presents a fresh perspective on one of the great classics of moral philosophy: Aristotle's Nicomachaen Ethics. He argues that it is, and deserves to be, Aristotle's most widely studied work, for much of what it has to say is still important for today's debate on the problems of ethics. Here, Bostock guides the reader through explanations and evaluations of all the main themes of the work, exploring questions of interpretation and the differing views of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   53 citations  
  • Love and friendship in Plato and Aristotle.A. W. Price - 1989 - New York: Oxford University Press.
    This book explores for the first time an idea common to both Plato and Aristotle: although people are separate, their lives need not be; one person's life may overflow into another's, so that helping someone else is a way of serving oneself. Price considers how this idea unites the philosophers' treatments of love and friendship (which are otherwise very different), and demonstrates that this view of love and friendship, applied not only to personal relationships, but also to the household and (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   62 citations  
  • Friendship, Self-Love, and Concern for Others in Aristotle’s Ethics.Dennis McKerlie - 1991 - Ancient Philosophy 11 (1):85-101.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Aristotle and altruism.Charles Kahn - 1981 - Mind 90 (357):20-40.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   22 citations  
  • Friendship, Self-Love, and Concern for Others in Aristotle’s Ethics.Dennis McKerlie - 1991 - Ancient Philosophy 11 (1):85-101.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Aristotle on the Utility and Choiceworthiness of Friends.D. Matthew - 2014 - Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie 96 (2):151-182.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Happy Lives and the Highest Good: An Essay on Aristotle's "Nicomachean Ethics".Gabriel Richardson Lear - 2005 - Princeton University Press.
    Gabriel Richardson Lear presents a bold new approach to one of the enduring debates about Aristotle's Nicomachean Ethics: the controversy about whether it coherently argues that the best life for humans is one devoted to a single activity, namely philosophical contemplation. Many scholars oppose this reading because the bulk of the Ethics is devoted to various moral virtues--courage and generosity, for example--that are not in any obvious way either manifestations of philosophical contemplation or subordinated to it. They argue that Aristotle (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   42 citations  
  • Aristotle on the Human Good.Richard Kraut - 1989 - Princeton University Press.
    Aristotle's Nicomachean Ethics, which equates the ultimate end of human life with happiness, is thought by many readers to argue that this highest goal consists in the largest possible aggregate of intrinsic goods. Richard Kraut proposes instead that Aristotle identifies happiness with only one type of good: excellent activity of the rational soul. In defense of this reading, Kraut discusses Aristotle's attempt to organize all human goods into a single structure, so that each subordinate end is desirable for the sake (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   82 citations  
  • When Aristotelian virtuous agents acquire the fine for themselves, what are they acquiring?Bradford Jean-Hyuk Kim - 2020 - British Journal for the History of Philosophy 28 (4):674-692.
    In the Nicomachean Ethics, one of Aristotle’s most frequent characterizations of the virtuous agent is that she acts for the sake of the fine (to kalon). In IX.8, this pursuit of the fine receives a more specific description; virtuous agents maximally assign the fine to themselves. In this paper, I answer the question of how we are to understand the fine as individually and maximally acquirable. I analyze Nicomachean Ethics IX.7, where Aristotle highlights virtuous activity (energeia) as central to the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Aristotle on Friendship and the Lovable.Bradford Jean-Hyuk Kim - 2021 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 59 (2):221-245.
    In this paper, I argue that Aristotle's basic principle, that all friends love only because of the lovable, is egoistic. First, I argue that 'the lovable' (τὸ φιλητὸν) refers to that which appears to contribute to one's own happiness. Second, I argue that the lovable is the final cause of love. This means that in loving only because of the lovable, all friends love only for the sake of what appears to contribute to their own happiness. Further, Aristotelian love for (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Εὺ́νοια.Peter Hadreas - 1995 - Ancient Philosophy 15 (2):393-402.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • ‘Friendship’ and ‘Self-Sufficiency’ in Homer and Aristotle.A. W. H. Adkins - 1963 - Classical Quarterly 13 (1):30-45.
    This article falls into two parts: the first is an analysis, in the light of my earlier discussions of and of the Homeric usage of and the second, an attempt to show that, as in the case of the effects of Homeric usage persist to a considerable degree in the moral philosophy of Aristotle. In the earlier discussions I have argued that the higher value placed upon the competitive in Greek entails that co-operative relationships, even when valued and necessary, take (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Love and Friendship in Plato and Aristotle.Anthony Price - 1990 - Mind 99 (395):487-489.
    Book synopsis: Reissued in 1997 with corrections and a new Afterword, this book fully explores for the first time an idea common to Plato and Aristotle, which unites their treatments - otherwise very different - of love and friendship. The idea is that although persons are separate, their lives need not be. One person's life may overflow into another's, and as such, helping another person is a way of serving oneself. The author shows how their view of love and friendship, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   53 citations  
  • Teleological Causation.David Charles - 2012 - In Christopher John Shields (ed.), The Oxford Handbook of Aristotle. Oxford University Press USA.
    Aristotle introduces the fourth cause, the teleological cause, in Physics II 3, based on the idea of something's being for the sake of a goal: the good to be achieved. The goal causes an activity to occur or an instrument to exist. They happen or exist because of some good that results from them. While Aristotle discerns teleological causation in a wide range of cases, these passages contain his key thought. Some things happen or exist because of some further good (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Impersonal Friends.Jennifer E. Whiting - 1991 - The Monist 74 (1):3-29.
    The rationality of concern for oneself has been taken for granted by the authors of western moral and political thought in a way in which the rationality of concern for others has not. While various authors have differed about the morality of self-concern, and about the extent to which such concern is rationally required, few have doubted that we have at least some special reasons to care for our selves, reasons that differ either in degree or in kind from those (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Aristotle on the Utility and Choiceworthiness of Friends.Matthew D. Walker - 2014 - Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie 96 (2):151-182.
    Aristotle’s views on the choiceworthiness of friends might seem both internally inconsistent and objectionably instrumentalizing. On the one hand, Aristotle maintains that perfect friends or virtue friends are choiceworthy and lovable for their own sake, and not merely for the sake of further ends. On the other hand, in Nicomachean Ethics IX.9, Aristotle appears somehow to account for the choiceworthiness of such friends by reference to their utility as sources of a virtuous agent’s robust self-awareness. I examine Aristotle’s views on (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • The Nicomachean Ethics. Aristotle - 1951 - Revue Philosophique de la France Et de l'Etranger 143:477-478.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   553 citations  
  • Nicomachean Ethics, Books VIII and IX. Aristotle - 1998
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Plato and Aristotle on friendship and altruism.Julia Annas - 1977 - Mind 86 (344):532-554.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   41 citations  
  • Aristotle on the friendships of utility and pleasure.Kenneth D. Alpern - 1983 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 21 (3):303-315.
    Utility- and pleasure-Friendship in the "nicomachean ethics" have commonly been held to be wholly self-Seeking relationships and of no great interest as forms of "friendship". Recently, John cooper has argued that these relationships essentially involve disinterested concern in a subtle blending of self- and other-Regarding purposes and causes. The article argues against cooper that disinterestedness has no part in these relationships but that they can nonetheless be seen as exhibiting trust, Sharing, Interdependence, And other virtues of interpersonal relationships.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • ‘Friendship’ and ‘Self-Sufficiency’ in Homer and Aristotle.A. W. H. Adkins - 1963 - Classical Quarterly 13 (01):30-.
    This article falls into two parts: the first is an analysis, in the light of my earlier discussions of and of the Homeric usage of and the second, an attempt to show that, as in the case of the effects of Homeric usage persist to a considerable degree in the moral philosophy of Aristotle. In the earlier discussions I have argued that the higher value placed upon the competitive in Greek entails that co-operative relationships, even when valued and necessary, take (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • ‘Friendship’ and ‘Self-Sufficiency’ in Homer and Aristotle.A. W. H. Adkins - 1919 - Classical Quarterly 13 (1):30-45.
    This article falls into two parts: the first is an analysis, in the light of my earlier discussions of and of the Homeric usage of and the second, an attempt to show that, as in the case of the effects of Homeric usage persist to a considerable degree in the moral philosophy of Aristotle. In the earlier discussions I have argued that the higher value placed upon the competitive in Greek entails that co-operative relationships, even when valued and necessary, take (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • The nicomachean account of philia.Jennifer Whiting - 2006 - In Richard Kraut (ed.), The Blackwell Guide to Aristotle’s Nicomachean Ethics. Oxford: Wiley-Blackwell. pp. 276--304.
    The prelims comprise: Preliminary Note Eudaimonism and Rational Egoism NE VIII.1: Nicomachean Context and Platonic Background NE VIII.2: Aristotle's Preliminary Account NE VIII.3–4: Three Forms of Philia? NE IX.4–6: Ta Philika versus the Defining Features of Philia Digression on Dia: Efficient Causal, Final Causal, or Both? NE IX.7 (VIII.8 and 12): Benefactors, Poets, and Parents Ethnocentrism and Aristotle's Ethocentric Ideal NE IX.9: The Lysis Puzzle Revisited Contemplative (versus Engaged) Pleasures Conclusion: Eudaimonism Revisited Conclusions Notes Reference.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  • (1 other version)Eudaimonia, External Results, and Choosing Virtuous Actions for Themselves.Jennifer Whiting - 2002 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 65 (2):270-290.
    Aristotle’s requirement that virtuous actions be chosen for themselves is typically interpreted, in Kantian terms, as taking virtuous action to have intrinsic rather than consequentialist value. This raises problems about how to reconcile Aristotle’s requirement with (a) the fact that virtuous actions typically aim at ends beyond themselves (usually benefits to others); and (b) Aristotle’s apparent requirement that everything (including virtuous action) be chosen for the sake of eudaimonia. I offer an alternative interpretation, based on Aristotle’s account of loving a (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  • Other Selves: Aristotle on Personal and Political Friendship.Paul Schollmeier - 1994 - State University of New York Press.
    This book presents a thorough and systematic integration of Aristotle's analysis of friendship with the main lines of the rest of his work in Politics and Nicomachean Ethics.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Aristotle and the Philosophy of Friendship.Lorraine Smith Pangle - 2002 - New York: Cambridge University Press.
    This book offers a comprehensive account of the major philosophical works on friendship and its relationship to self-love. The book gives central place to Aristotle's searching examination of friendship in the Nicomachean Ethics. Lorraine Pangle argues that the difficulties surrounding this discussion are soon dispelled once one understands the purpose of the Ethics as both a source of practical guidance for life and a profound, theoretical investigation into human nature. The book also provides fresh interpretations of works on friendship by (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   23 citations  
  • Character and The Forms of Friendship in Aristotle.Andrew Payne - 2000 - Apeiron 33 (1):53 - 74.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Aristotle on loving another for his own sake.Kelly Rogers - 1994 - Phronesis 39 (3):291-302.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   21 citations  
  • (1 other version)Eudaimonia, external results, and choosing virtuous actions for themselves.Jennifer Whiting - 2002 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 65 (2):270-290.
    Aristotle's requirement that virtuous actions be chosen for themselves is typically interpreted, in Kantian terms, as taking virtuous action to have intrinsic rather than consequentialist value. This raises problems about how to reconcile Aristotle's requirement with (a) the fact that virtuous actions typically aim at ends beyond themselves (usually benefits to others); and (b) Aristotle's apparent requirement that everything (including virtuous action) be chosen for the sake of eudaimonia. I offer an alternative interpretation, based on Aristotle's account of loving a (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   20 citations  
  • (1 other version)Notes on the Nicomachean Ethics of Aristotle.J. A. Stewart & J. E. C. Welldon - 1893 - International Journal of Ethics 4 (1):123-126.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   32 citations  
  • Aristotle on the Good of Virtue-Friendship.D. N. Schroeder - 1992 - History of Political Thought 13 (2):203.
    Aristotle's well-known divisions of friendship, those based on utility, pleasure and virtue, are based on the kind of good each provides. It is fairly easy to see what is contributed by utility- and pleasure-friendships, but virtue-friendship presents a special difficulty. Aristotle writes that virtue-friendship occurs between good (virtuous) persons, each of whom is happy because of that goodness. Aristotle also asserts, however, that the good (happy) person, especially the philosopher, is largely self-sufficient, needing little in the way of external goods (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • (1 other version)Aristotelian Philia, Modern Friendship.Alexander Nehamas - 2010 - Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 39:213 - 248.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • (1 other version)Notes on the Nichomachean Ethics of Aristotle.J. Stewart - 1893 - Philosophical Review 2:120.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   22 citations