Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. Adoption is Not Abortion‐Lite.Lindsey Porter - 2012 - Journal of Applied Philosophy 29 (1):63-78.
    abstract It is standardly taken for granted in the literature on the morality of abortion that adoption is almost always an available and morally preferable alternative to abortion — one that does the same thing so far as parenthood is concerned. This assumption pushes proponents of a woman's right to choose into giving arguments that are based almost exclusively around the physicality of pregnancy and childbirth. On the other side of the debate, the assumption that adoption is a real alternative (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Why and How to Prefer a Causal Account of Parenthood.Lindsey Porter - 2014 - Journal of Social Philosophy 45 (2):182-202.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • (1 other version)Rescuing the Duty to Rescue.Tina Rulli & Joseph Millum - 2014 - Journal of Medical Ethics:1-5.
    Clinicians and health researchers frequently encounter opportunities to rescue people. Rescue cases can generate a moral duty to aid those in peril. As such, bioethicists have leveraged a duty to rescue for a variety of purposes. Yet, despite its broad application, the duty to rescue is under-analyzed. In this paper, we assess the state of theorizing about the duty to rescue. There are large gaps in bioethicists’ understanding of the force, scope, and justification of the two most cited duties to (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   25 citations  
  • An Orwellian Scenario: court ordered caesarean section and women’s autonomy.Heather Cahill - 1999 - Nursing Ethics 6 (6):494-505.
    Between 1992 and 1996, a small number of women in the UK were forced by the courts to undergo caesarean section against their expressed refusal. Analysis of the reported cases reveals the blanket assumption of maternal incompetence and the widespread use of thinly veiled coercion. Such attitudes and practices are themselves frequently compounded by inadequate communication. Medical discretion in such problematic cases seems to err on the side of safety and so appears to favour the life of the fetus over (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Are pregnant women fetal containers?Laura M. Purdy - 1990 - Bioethics 4 (4):273–291.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  • Were You a Part of Your Mother?Elselijn Kingma - 2019 - Mind 128 (511):609-646.
    Is the mammalian embryo/fetus a part of the organism that gestates it? According to the containment view, the fetus is not a part of, but merely contained within or surrounded by, the gestating organism. According to the parthood view, the fetus is a part of the gestating organism. This paper proceeds in two stages. First, I argue that the containment view is the received view; that it is generally assumed without good reason; and that it needs substantial support if it (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   64 citations  
  • Parental Obligations Regarding Fetal Risk: Finding the Appropriate Analogy.Janet Malek - 2016 - American Journal of Bioethics 16 (2):27-28.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Future people, involuntary medical treatment in pregnancy and the duty of easy rescue.Julian Savulescu - 2007 - Utilitas 19 (1):1-20.
    I argue that pregnant women have a duty to refrain from behaviours or to allow certain acts to be done to them for the sake of their foetus if the foetus has a reasonable chance of living and being in a harmed state if the woman does not refrain from those behaviours or allow those things to be done to her. There is a proviso: that her refraining from acting or allowing acts to be performed upon her does not significantly (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  • II. The Gift of Life.J. David Velleman - 2008 - Philosophy and Public Affairs 36 (3):245-266.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  • Moral Agency and the Family: The Case of Living Related Organ Transplantation.Robert A. Crouch & Carl Elliott - 1999 - Cambridge Quarterly of Healthcare Ethics 8 (3):275-287.
    Living related organ transplantation is morally problematic for two reasons. First, it requires surgeons to perform nontherapeutic, even dangerous procedures on healthy donors—and in the case of children, without their consent. Second, the transplant donor and recipient are often intimately related to each other, as parent and child, or as siblings. These relationships challenge our conventional models of medical decisionmaking. Is there anything morally problematic about a parent allowing the interests of one child to be risked for the sake of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   35 citations  
  • Law and the Life Sciences: Forced Cesareans: The Most Unkindest Cut of All.George J. Annas - 1982 - Hastings Center Report 12 (3):16.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Coercion and choice in parent–child live kidney donation.Philippa Burnell, Sally-Anne Hulton & Heather Draper - 2015 - Journal of Medical Ethics 41 (4):304-309.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Finding autonomy in birth.Rebecca Kukla, Miriam Kuppermann, Margaret Little, Anne Drapkin Lyerly, Lisa M. Mitchell, Elizabeth M. Armstrong & Lisa Harris - 2008 - Bioethics 23 (1):1-8.
    Over the last several years, as cesarean deliveries have grown increasingly common, there has been a great deal of public and professional interest in the phenomenon of women 'choosing' to deliver by cesarean section in the absence of any specific medical indication. The issue has sparked intense conversation, as it raises questions about the nature of autonomy in birth. Whereas mainstream bioethical discourse is used to associating autonomy with having a large array of choices, this conception of autonomy does not (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • Women, forced caesareans and antenatal responsibilities.H. Draper - 1996 - Journal of Medical Ethics 22 (6):327-333.
    In the UK in October 1992, Mrs S was forced to have a caesarean section despite her objections to such a procedure on religious grounds. The case once again called into question the obligations of women to the unborn, and also whether one person can be forced to undergo a medical procedure for the benefit of someone else. Re S, like the case of Angela Carder, is often discussed in terms of the conflict between maternal and fetal rights. This paper (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • (1 other version)Rescuing the duty to rescue.Tina Rulli & Joseph Millum - 2016 - Journal of Medical Ethics 42 (4):260-264.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   23 citations  
  • Donation, Surrogacy and Adoption.Edgar Page - 1985 - Journal of Applied Philosophy 2 (2):161-172.
    ABSTRACT The Warnock Report fails to reveal an important underlying principle concerning the donation and transference of gametes and embryos. This principle contrasts sharply with the principle that children are non‐transferable. Consideration of where to place the line between transferable embryos and non‐transferable fetuses, or children, yields a conception of surrogacy that would set it apart from adoption. The paper argues for a coherent system of surrogacy supported by regulative institutions in which surrogacy is seen to facilitate an acceptable form (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations