Switch to: Citations

References in:

Kant’s Standpoint Distinction

Kantian Review 23 (2):229-255 (2018)

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. Kant's Transcendental Idealism.Jill Vance Buroker - 1986 - Noûs 20 (4):577.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   111 citations  
  • Things in themselves.Robert Merrihew Adams - 1997 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 57 (4):801-825.
    The paper is an interpretation and defense of Kant's conception of things in themselves as noumena, along the following lines. Noumena are transempirical realities. As such they have several important roles in Kant's critical philosophy (Section 1). Our theoretical faculties cannot obtain enough content for a conception of noumena that would assure their real possibility as objects, but can establish their merely formal logical possibility (Sections 2-3). Our practical reason, however, grounds belief in the real possibility of some noumena, and (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   39 citations  
  • Dignity and Practical Reason in Kant's Moral Theory.Thomas E. Hill - 1992 - Ithaca: Cornell University Press.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   65 citations  
  • Problems from Van Cleve's Kant: Experience and Objects.Karl Ameriks - 2003 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 66 (1):196-202.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   33 citations  
  • Kant on the Nature of Logical Laws.Clinton Tolley - 2006 - Philosophical Topics 34 (1-2):371-407.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   33 citations  
  • Constructions of Reason: Explorations of Kant's Practical Philosophy.Nelson Potter - 1993 - Noûs 27 (3):386-388.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   59 citations  
  • Two Standpoints and the Belief in Freedom.Dana K. Nelkin - 2000 - Journal of Philosophy 97 (10):564.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  • Kantian Humility: Our Ignorance of Things in Themselves.A. W. Moore - 2001 - Philosophical Review 110 (1):117.
    Kant once wrote, “Many historians of philosophy... let the philosophers speak mere nonsense.... They cannot see beyond what the philosophers actually said to what they really meant to say.’ Rae Langton begins her book with this quotation. She concludes it, after a final pithy summary of the position that she attributes to Kant, with the comment, “That, it seems to me, is what Kant said, and meant to say”. In between are some two hundred pages of admirably clear, tightly argued (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   62 citations  
  • Kant on Determinism and the Categorical Imperative.Markus Kohl - 2015 - Ethics 125 (2):331-356.
    I provide a sympathetic reconstruction of Kant’s motivation for endorsing incompatibilism about human freedom. On my interpretation, Kant holds that if all the determining grounds of our actions were subject to natural necessity, we would never be free to respect or defy laws of practical reason, and for Kant such freedom is a condition for the possibility that our actions are governed by categorical imperatives. I argue that his view rests on a gripping construal of the rational imperfection that afflicts (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Kant on Freedom of Empirical Thought.Markus Kohl - 2015 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 53 (2):301-26.
    It is standardly assumed that, in Kant, “free agency” is identical to moral agency and requires the will or practical reason. Likewise, it is often held that the concept of “spontaneity” that Kant uses in his theoretical philosophy is very different from, and much thinner than, his idea of practical spontaneity. In this paper I argue for the contrary view: Kant has a rich theory of doxastic free agency, and the spontaneity in empirical thought (which culminates in judgments of experience) (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • Kant on Idealism, Freedom, and Standpoints.Markus Kohl - 2016 - Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie 98 (1):21-54.
    I propose a new way of understanding Kant’s doctrine of freedom. My reading seeks to combine features of two popular opposed lines of interpretation, namely, of metaphysical and anti-metaphysical readings. I defend the view that Kant’s idealist attempt to ‘save’ human freedom involves substantive metaphysical commitments. However, I show that this interpretation can fruitfully integrate important insights that are standardly associated with deflationary readings: first, the idea that for Kant freedom and natural necessity can be ascribed to one and the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Three kinds of rationalism and the non-spatiality of things in themselves.Desmond Hogan - 2009 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 47 (3):pp. 355-382.
    In the transcendental aesthetic of the Critique of Pure Reason, Kant claims that space and time are neither things in themselves nor properties of things in themselves but mere subjective forms of our sensible experience. Call this the Subjectivity Thesis. The striking conclusion follows an analysis of the representations of space and time. Kant argues that the two representations function as a priori conditions of experience, and are singular "intuitions" rather than general concepts. He also contends that the representations underwrite (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   32 citations  
  • Kant's System of Perspectives: An Architectonic Interpretation of the Critical Philosophy.Stephen R. PALMQUIST - 1993
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   24 citations  
  • Kant's Transcendental Idealism and the Categories.Eric Watkins - 2002 - History of Philosophy Quarterly 19 (2):191 - 215.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations