Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. Kant's aesthetic theory.Donald W. Crawford - 1974 - [Madison]: University of Wisconsin Press.
    Immanuel Kant was a German philosopher. He is a central figure of modern philosophy, and set the terms by which all subsequent thinkers have had to grapple. He argued that human perception structures natural laws, and that reason is the source of morality. His thought continues to hold a major influence in contemporary thought, especially in fields such as metaphysics, epistemology, ethics, political philosophy, and aesthetics.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   27 citations  
  • The Schematism and Empirical Concepts.Robert B. Pippin - 1976 - Kant Studien 67 (1-4):156-171.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  • Kant’s Theory of Taste: A Reading of the Critique of Aesthetic Judgment.Henry Allison - 2001 - New York: Cambridge University Press.
    This book constitutes one of the most important contributions to recent Kant scholarship. In it, one of the pre-eminent interpreters of Kant, Henry Allison, offers a comprehensive, systematic, and philosophically astute account of all aspects of Kant's views on aesthetics. The first part of the book analyses Kant's conception of reflective judgment and its connections with both empirical knowledge and judgments of taste. The second and third parts treat two questions that Allison insists must be kept distinct: the normativity of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   121 citations  
  • The truth in painting.Jacques Derrida - 1987 - Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
    "The four essays in this volume constitute Derrida's most explicit and sustained reflection on the art work as pictorial artifact, a reflection partly by way of philosophical aesthetics (Kant, Heidegger), partly by way of a commentary on art works and art scholarship (Van Gogh, Adami, Titus-Carmel). The illustrations are excellent, and the translators, who clearly see their work as both a rendering and a transformation, add yet another dimension to this richly layered composition. Indispensable to collections emphasizing art criticism and (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   55 citations  
  • Aesthetics and Material Beauty: Aesthetics Naturalized.Jennifer McMahon - 2007 - New York: Routledge. Edited by Michael Beaney.
    In _Aesthetics and Material Beauty_, Jennifer A. McMahon develops a new aesthetic theory she terms Critical Aesthetic Realism - taking Kantian aesthetics as a starting point and drawing upon contemporary theories of mind from philosophy, psychology, and cognitive science. The creative process does not proceed by a set of rules. Yet the fact that its objects can be understood or appreciated by others suggests that the creative process is constrained by principles to which others have access. According to her update (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • Aesthetic Experience: Beauty, Creativity, and the Search for the Ideal.George Hagman (ed.) - 2005 - BRILL.
    "George Hagman looks anew at psychoanalytic ideas about art and beauty through the lens of current developmental psychology that recognizes the importance of attachment and affiliative motivational systems. In dialogue with theorists such as Freud, Ehrenzweig, Kris, Rank, Winnicott, Kohut, and many others, Hagman brings the psychoanalytic understanding of aesthetic experience into the 21st century. He amends and extends old concepts and offers a wealth of stimulating new ideas regarding the creative process, the ideal, beauty, ugliness, and -perhaps his most (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • The Kantian sublime: from morality to art.Paul Crowther - 1989 - New York: Oxford University Press.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   25 citations  
  • Imagination and interpretation in Kant: the hermeneutical import of the Critique of judgment.Rudolf A. Makkreel - 1990 - Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
    In this illuminating study of Kant's theory of imagination and its role in interpretation, Rudolf A. Makkreel argues against the commonly held notion that Kant's transcendental philosophy is incompatible with hermeneutics. The charge that Kant's foundational philosophy is inadequate to the task of interpretation can be rebutted, explains Makkreel, if we fully understand the role of imagination in his work. In identifying this role, Makkreel also reevaluates the relationship among Kant's discussions of the feeling of life, common sense, and the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   51 citations  
  • The Kantian aesthetic: from knowledge to the avant-garde.Paul Crowther - 2010 - New York: Oxford University Press.
    This is done by exploring some of his other ideas concerning how critical comparisons inform our cultivation of taste, and art's relation to genius.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • The Idea of Form: Rethinking Kant’s Aesthetics.Rodolphe Gasché - 2002 - Stanford, Calif.: Stanford University Press.
    Against the assumption that aesthetic form relates to a harmonious arrangement of parts into a beautiful whole, this book argues that reason is the real theme of the _Critique of Judgment_ as of the two earlier _Critiques_. Since aesthetic judgment of the beautiful becomes possible only when the mind is confronted with things of nature, for which no determined concepts of understanding are available, aesthetic judgment is involved in an epistemological or, rather, para-epistemological task. The predicate "beautiful" indicates that something (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Interpreting Kant's Critiques.Karl Ameriks - 2003 - New York: Oxford University Press.
    Karl Ameriks here collects his most important essays to provide a uniquely detailed and up-to-date analysis of Kant's main arguments in all three major areas of his work: theoretical philosophy (Critique of Pure Reason), practical philosophy (Critique of Practical Reason), and aesthetics (Critique of Judgment). Guiding the volume is Ameriks's belief that one cannot properly understand any one of these Critiques except in the context of the other two. The essays can be read individually, but read together they offer a (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   72 citations  
  • The Pleasures of Contra‐purposiveness: Kant, the Sublime, and Being Human.Katerina Deligiorgi - 2014 - Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 72 (1):25-35.
    Serious doubts have been raised about the coherence of theories of the sublime and the usefulness of the concept. By contrast, the sublime is increasingly studied as a key function in Kant's moral psychology and in his ethics. This article combines methodological conservatism, approaching the topic from within Kant's discussion of aesthetic judgment, with reconstruction of a conception of human agency that is tenable on Kantian grounds. I argue that a coherent theory of the sublime is possible and useful, and (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Geist and Communication in Kant's Theory of Aesthetic Ideas.Charles DeBord - 2012 - Kantian Review 17 (2):177-190.
    In hisCritique of the Power of Judgement, Kant explicates the creation of works of fine art (schöne Kunst) in terms of aesthetic ideas. His analysis of aesthetic ideas claims that they are not concepts (Begriffe) and are therefore not definable or describable in determinate language. Nevertheless, Kant claims that aesthetic ideas are communicable via spirit (Geist), a special mental ability he associates with artistic genius. This paper argues that Kant's notion ofGeistis central to his analysis of fine art's expressive power. (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Embodied meanings, isotypes, and aesthetical ideas.Arthur C. Danto - 2007 - Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 65 (1):121–129.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   22 citations  
  • The harmony of reason: a study in Kant's aesthetics.Francis X. J. Coleman - 1974 - [Pittsburg]: University of Pittsburgh Press.
    Introduction The General Bearings of Kant's Third Critique The Critique of Judgment may be broadly viewed as a work of philosophical diplomacy in which Kant ...
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Three problems in Kant's aesthetics.Ted Cohen - 2002 - British Journal of Aesthetics 42 (1):1-12.
    What does the faculty of Understanding do during the execution of a judgement of taste? How are singular judgements of beauty related to general judgements of beauty? For what reason is beauty the symbol of morality? The first question has a tentative answer, although one not obviously congenial to Kant. The second two questions have no compelling answers.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • An emendation in Kant's theory of taste.Ted Cohen - 1990 - Noûs 24 (1):137-145.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • A Case for Kantian Artistic Sublimity: A Response to Abaci.Robert R. Clewis - 2010 - Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 68 (2):167-170.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Kant on the normativity of taste: The role of aesthetic ideas.Andrew Chignell - 2007 - Australasian Journal of Philosophy 85 (3):415 – 433.
    For Kant, the form of a subject's experience of an object provides the normative basis for an aesthetic judgement about it. In other words, if the subject's experience of an object has certain structural properties, then Kant thinks she can legitimately judge that the object is beautiful - and that it is beautiful for everyone. My goal in this paper is to provide a new account of how this 'subjective universalism' is supposed to work. In doing so, I appeal to (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   31 citations  
  • Kant's Aesthetic Epistemology. [REVIEW]Fiona Hughes - 2010 - Kantian Review 14 (2):155.
    Drawing on resources from both the analytical and continental traditions, this book argues that a comprehension of Immanuel Kant's aesthetics is necessary for grasping the scope and force of his epistemology. It draws on phenomenological and aesthetic resources to bring out the continuing relevance of Kant's project. One of the difficulties faced in reading ‘The Critique of Pure Reason’ is finding a way of reading the text as one continuous discussion. This book offers a reading at each stage of Kant's (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • The sense of ugliness.Peter A. Carmichael - 1972 - Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 30 (4):495-498.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Logical purposiveness and the principle of taste.Luigi Caranti - 2005 - Kant Studien 96 (3):364-374.
    In both Introductions to the Critique of Judgment Kant seems to identify the a priori principle at the basis of aesthetic judgments with the principle that guides reflective judgment in its cognitive inquiry of nature, i.e. the purposiveness of nature or systematicity. For instance Kant writes.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • The Philosophy of Horror or Paradoxes of the Heart.Noel Carroll - 1991 - Philosophical Quarterly 41 (165):519.
    Noel Carroll, film scholar and philosopher, offers the first serious look at the aesthetics of horror. In this book he discusses the nature and narrative structures of the genre, dealing with horror as a "transmedia" phenomenon. A fan and serious student of the horror genre, Carroll brings to bear his comprehensive knowledge of obscure and forgotten works, as well as of the horror masterpieces. Working from a philosophical perspective, he tries to account for how people can find pleasure in having (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   71 citations  
  • Ugliness and Nature.Emily Brady - 2010 - Enrahonar: Quaderns de Filosofía 45:27-40.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • Kant's principle of purposiveness and the missing point of (aesthetic) judgements.Avner Baz - 2005 - Kantian Review 10:1-32.
    My plan in this article is to begin by raising the question of the point of judgements of beauty, and then to examine Kant's account of beauty in the third Critique from the perspective opened up by that question. Having raised the question of the point, I will argue, first, that there is an implied answer to it in Kant's text, and, second, that the answer is ultimately unsatisfying in that it falsely assumes that there is a ‘need’, or ‘task’, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Subjektivität, Allgemeingültigkeit und Apriorität des Geschmacksurteils bei Kant.Manfred Baum - 1991 - Deutsche Zeitschrift für Philosophie 39 (3):272-284.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • The Problem of Free Harmony in Kant's Aesthetics.Kenneth F. Rogerson - 2008 - State University of New York Press.
    _A study of the first half of Kant’s Critique of Judgment._.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Kant's metaphysic of experience.H. J. Paton - 1936 - London,: G. Allen & Unwin.
    Originally published: London: Allen & Unwin, 1936.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   64 citations  
  • The Purposiveness of Form: A Reading of Kant's Aesthetic Formalism.Rachel Zuckert - 2006 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 44 (4):599-622.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Journal of the History of Philosophy 44.4 (2006) 599-622 MuseSearchJournalsThis JournalContents[Access article in PDF]The Purposiveness of Form: A Reading of Kant's Aesthetic FormalismRachel ZuckertIn the "critique of aesthetic judgment," Kant claims that when we find an object beautiful, we are appreciating its "purposive form." Many of Kant's readers have found this claim one of his least interesting and most easily criticized claims about aesthetic experience. Detractors hold up his (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Duchamp And Kant: Together at Last.Robert J. Yanal - 2002 - Angelaki 7 (1):161-167.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Kant on fine art: Artistic sublimity shaped by beauty.Robert Wicks - 1995 - Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 53 (2):189-193.
    This essay critically examines the view recently set forth by Paul Guyer that Kant's theories of artistic beauty and artistic creativity exclusively coincide with this theory of natural beauty. I note that very great works of art, although they may indeed be beautiful, also tend to be sublime. To acknowledge the sense of awe which attends those great works of art which are also beautiful, I argue that Kant's theory of sublimity must also be included within an accurate interpretation of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Kant and the Capacity to Judge.Kenneth R. Westphal & Beatrice Longuenesse - 2000 - Philosophical Review 109 (4):645.
    Kant famously declares that “although all our cognition commences with experience, … it does not on that account all arise from experience”. This marks Kant’s disagreement with empiricism, and his contention that human knowledge and experience require both sensation and the use of certain a priori concepts, the Categories. However, this is only the surface of Kant’s much deeper, though neglected view about the nature of reason and judgment. Kant holds that even our a priori concepts are acquired, not from (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   230 citations  
  • Kant finds nothing ugly?Christian Wenzel - 1999 - British Journal of Aesthetics 39 (4):416-422.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • Schematism.W. H. Walsh - 1957 - Kant Studien 49 (1-4):95-106.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Kant's Justified Dismissal of Artistic Sublimity.Uygar Abaci - 2008 - Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 66 (3):237 - 251.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Das Häßliche und die „Kritik der ästhetischen Urteilskraft“. Überlegungen zu einer systematischen Lücke.Christian Strub - 1989 - Kant Studien 80 (1-4):416-446.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Free Beauty, Dependent Beauty, and Art.Robert Stecker - 1987 - The Journal of Aesthetic Education 21 (1):89.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • The paradox of painful art.Aaron Smuts - 2007 - Journal of Aesthetic Education 41 (3):59-77.
    Many of the most popular genres of narrative art are designed to elicit negative emotions: emotions that are experienced as painful or involving some degree of pain, which we generally avoid in our daily lives. Melodramas make us cry. Tragedies bring forth pity and fear. Conspiratorial thrillers arouse feelings of hopelessness and dread, and devotional religious art can make the believer weep in sorrow. Not only do audiences know what these artworks are supposed to do; they seek them out in (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   23 citations  
  • Why Kant finds nothing ugly.David Shier - 1998 - British Journal of Aesthetics 38 (4):412-418.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  • The harmony of the faculties.Fred L. Rush - 2001 - Kant Studien 92 (1):38-61.
    The primary task confronting an examination of the claimed connection between Kant's general theory of cognition and his account of aesthetic judgment requires clarifying perhaps the most obscure component of that account, the doctrine of the harmony of the faculties. Kant's presentation of this doctrine makes it notoriously difficult to penetrate. Much of what Kant says about the harmony of the faculties – perhaps the very phrase “the harmony of the faculties” – is rather imprecise and metaphorical. Yet, the importance (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  • The Free Play of the Faculties and the Status of Natural Beauty in Kant's Theory of Taste.Alexander Rueger - 2008 - Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie 90 (3):298-322.
    I argue that the free play of the faculties in Kant's theory of beauty should be interpreted as an activity that involves, over and above cognition, the aesthetic presentation of rational ideas. Two consequences of this proposal are then discussed: (1) Beauty in nature is not systematically prior to, or more basic than, artificial beauty; (2) genius and taste are connected more closely in the notion of the free play than Kant admits in the final version of his theory; this (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • The role of symbolic presentation in Kant's theory of taste.Alexander Rueger & Sahan Evren - 2005 - British Journal of Aesthetics 45 (3):229-247.
    Beauty, or at least natural beauty, is famously a symbol of the morally good in Kant's theory of taste. Natural beauty is also, we argue, a symbol of the systematicity of nature. This symbolic connection of beauty and systematicity in nature sheds light on the relation between the principles underlying the use of reflecting judgement. The connection also motivates a more general interpretive proposal: the fact that the imagination can symbolize ideas plays a crucial role in the theory of taste; (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  • Beautiful surfaces: Kant on free and adherent beauty in nature and art.Alexander Rueger - 2008 - British Journal for the History of Philosophy 16 (3):535 – 557.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Kant's Aesthetics: The Roles of Form and Expression.Kenneth F. Rogerson - 1989 - Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 47 (4):387-389.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • Can kants deduction of judgments of taste be saved?Miles Rind - 2002 - Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie 84 (1):20-45.
    Kant’s argument in § 38 of the *Critique of Judgment* is subject to a dilemma: if the subjective condition of cognition is the sufficient condition of the pleasure of taste, then every object of experience must produce that pleasure; if not, then the universal communicability of cognition does not entail the universal communicability of the pleasure. Kant’s use of an additional premise in § 21 may get him out of this difficulty, but the premises themselves hang in the air and (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • The psychology of ugliness.R. W. Pickford - 1969 - British Journal of Aesthetics 9 (3):258-270.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Placing ugliness in Kant's third critique : A reply to Paul Guyer.James Phillips - 2011 - Kant Studien 102 (3):385-395.
    Kant's treatment of pure aesthetic judgement can ignore ugliness, since an analytic of the ugly, according to a recent essay by Paul Guyer, uncovers the aesthetic impurity of the criteria against which we judge ugliness. Free beauty, as Kant expounds it, does not admit a contrary, and hence a Kantian account of ugliness, such as Guyer's, must look elsewhere in order to scrabble together terms for its definition. Yet if we recognise the ugly by its unsuitability as an object of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • On the beautiful and the ugly.Herman Parret - 2011 - Trans/Form/Ação 34 (s2):21-34.
    Classical aesthetics sees the experience of the beautiful as an anthropological necessity. But, in fact, the beautiful is rather the central category designating classical art, and one can question the relevance of this category considering contemporary art. The reference term most frequently used for contemporary art is interesting: works of art solicit the interests of my faculties (the cognitiveintellectual, the pragmatic community-oriented moral, the affective aesthetic faculties). It is interesting to notice that the categories of the beautiful and the ugly (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Kant on genius and art.Bradley Murray - 2007 - British Journal of Aesthetics 47 (2):199-214.
    The paper distinguishes between two different senses of ‘genius’ found in Kant's Critique of Judgement, and criticizes an argument commonly attributed to Kant. The argument is in support of the conclusion that an agent must possess and employ genius in the ‘productive faculty’ sense in order to produce an artwork. It is shown that Kant did not in fact make this argument. He defended a different claim concerning the need to employ the concept of a productive faculty of genius in (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Appreciating Natural Beauty as Natural.Ronald Moore - 1999 - The Journal of Aesthetic Education 33 (3):42.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations