Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. Divine Responsibility Without Divine Freedom.Michael Bergmann & J. A. Cover - 2006 - Faith and Philosophy 23 (4):381-408.
    Adherents of traditional western Theism have espoused CONJUNCTION: God is essentially perfectly good and God is thankworthy for the good acts he performs. But suppose that (i) God’s essential perfect goodness prevents his good acts from being free, and that (ii) God is not thankworthy for an act that wasn’t freely performed. Together these entail the denial of CONJUNCTION. The most natural strategy for defenders of CONJUNCTION is to deny (i). We develop an argument for (i), and then identify two (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • The Nature of Necessity.Alvin Plantinga - 1974 - Oxford, England: Clarendon Press.
    This book, one of the first full-length studies of the modalities to emerge from the debate to which Saul Kripke, David Lewis, Ruth Marcus, and others are contributing, is an exploration and defense of the notion of modality de re, the idea that objects have both essential and accidental properties. Plantinga develops his argument by means of the notion of possible worlds and ranges over such key problems as the nature of essence, transworld identity, negative existential propositions, and the existence (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   682 citations  
  • Defending Divine Freedom.Thomas D. Senor - 2013 - In L. Kvanvig Jonathan (ed.), Oxford Studies in Philosophy of Religion. Oxford University Press. pp. 168-95.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • On the nature and existence of God.Richard M. Gale - 1991 - New York: Cambridge University Press.
    There has been in recent years a plethora of defenses of theism from analytical philosophers such as Plantinga, Swinburne, and Alston. Richard Gale's important book is a critical response to these writings. New versions of cosmological, ontological, and religious experience arguments are critically evaluated, along with pragmatic arguments to justify faith on the grounds of its prudential or moral benefits. A special feature of the book is the discussion of the atheological argument that attempts to deduce a contradiction from the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  • Could Abstract Objects Depend upon God?Scott A. Davison - 1991 - Religious Studies 27 (4):485 - 497.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Could Abstract Objects Depend Upon God?: SCOTT A. DAVISON.Scott A. Davison - 1991 - Religious Studies 27 (4):485-497.
    What sorts of things are there in the world? Clearly enough, there are concrete, material things; but are there other things too, perhaps nonconcrete or non-material things? Some people believe that there are such things, which are often called abstract ; purported examples of such objects include numbers, properties, possible but non-actual states of affairs, propositions, and sets. Following a long-standing tradition, I shall describe persons who believe that there are abstract objects as ‘platonists’. In this paper, I shall not (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Creation and conservation once more.William Lane Craig - 1998 - Religious Studies 34 (2):177-188.
    God is conceived in the Western theistic tradition to be both the Creator and Conservor of the universe. These two roles were typically classed as different aspects of creation, originating creation and continuing creation. On pain of incoherence, however, conservation needs to be distinguished from creation. Contrary to current analyses (such as Philip Quinn's), creation should be explicated in terms of God's bringing something into being, while conservation should be understood in terms of God's preservation of something over an interval (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • The irrelevance of the no best possible world defense.Keith Chrzan - 1987 - Philosophia 17 (2):161-167.
    Certainly NBPW can justify metaphysical evil, which is all Leibniz intended it to do. Probably, as suggested by Bruce Reichenbach, NBPW can rebut an atheistic argument from the non-existence of the best possible world. It could even augment a GGD by defending against a divine obligation to have created a “larger” world. But NBPW by itself cannot serve to derail the logical problem of evil in any way whatsoever; theists must find refuge in a GGD if they are to find (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • The existence of God.Richard Swinburne - 1991 - New York: Oxford University Press.
    Richard Swinburne presents a substantially rewritten and updated edition of his most celebrated book. No other work has made a more powerful case for the probability of the existence of God. Swinburne gives a rigorous and penetrating analysis of the most important arguments for theism: the cosmological argument; arguments from the existence of laws of nature and the 'fine-tuning' of the universe; from the occurrence of consciousness and moral awareness; and from miracles and religious experience. He claims that while none (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   187 citations  
  • The world’s continuance: divine conservation or existential inertia?John Beaudoin - 2007 - International Journal for Philosophy of Religion 61 (2):83 - 98.
    According to the Doctrine of Divine Conservation, the world could not endure through time were God not actively sustaining its existence. An alternative to the conservationist view is one according to which the existence of whatever is the fundamental material of our universe is characterized by inertia, so that its continuance stands in no need of active causal intervention by some other being. In this article I develop in some detail the Doctrine of Existential Inertia and reply to some of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • In what sense must God be omnibenevolent?David Basinger - 1983 - International Journal for Philosophy of Religion 14 (1):3 - 15.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • In what sense must God do his best: A response to Hasker. [REVIEW]David Basinger - 1985 - International Journal for Philosophy of Religion 18 (3):161 - 164.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Divine Providence: The Molinist Account.David Basinger - 2000 - Philosophical Review 109 (2):274.
    Christian theists have always been concerned with the relationship between God’s providential control and human freedom. Flint’s book is an explication and defense of what he sees as the best way for orthodox Christians to conceive of this relationship: the Molinist account.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   24 citations  
  • God's general concurrence with secondary causes: Why conservation is not enough.Alfred J. Freddoso - 1991 - Philosophical Perspectives 5:553-585.
    After an exposition of some key concepts in scholastic ontology, this paper examines four arguments presented by Francisco Suarez for the thesis, commonly held by Christian Aristotelians, that God's causal contribution to effects occurring in the ordinary course of nature goes beyond His merely conserving created substances along with their active and passive causal powers. The postulation of a further causal contribution, known as God's general concurrence (or general concourse), can be viewed as an attempt to accommodate an element of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   41 citations  
  • Must God create the best?Robert Merrihew Adams - 1972 - Philosophical Review 81 (3):317-332.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   104 citations  
  • Warranted Christian Belief.Alvin Plantinga - 2000 - New York, US: Oxford University Press USA.
    This is the third volume in Alvin Plantinga's trilogy on the notion of warrant, which he defines as that which distinguishes knowledge from true belief. In this volume, Plantinga examines warrant's role in theistic belief, tackling the questions of whether it is rational, reasonable, justifiable, and warranted to accept Christian belief and whether there is something epistemically unacceptable in doing so. He contends that Christian beliefs are warranted to the extent that they are formed by properly functioning cognitive faculties, thus, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   309 citations  
  • Evil and the God of Love.John Hick - 1966 - Macmillan.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   110 citations  
  • Virtue, Vice and Value.Thomas Hurka - 2001 - Philosophical Quarterly 52 (208):413-415.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   163 citations  
  • Can God Choose a World at Random?Klaas J. Kraay - 2008 - In Yujin Nagasawa & Erik J. Wielenberg (eds.), New waves in philosophy of religion. New York: Palgrave-Macmillan.
    On what basis does God choose a possible world to make actual? Theists typically claim that God freely selects exactly one world on the basis of its axiological characteristics. But suppose that there are infinitely many unsurpassable worlds from which to choose; or else that there are no unsurpassable worlds, but instead an infinite hierarchy of increasingly better worlds. On each of these scenarios, philosophers have alleged that God is unable rationally to choose a world for actualization. In the former (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • The many-universes solution to the problem of evil.Donald Turner - 2003 - In Richard M. Gale & Alexander R. Pruss (eds.), The Existence of God. Ashgate Pub Limited.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  • Gratuitous Evil and Divine Existence.Keith Yandell - 1989 - Religious Studies 25 (1):15 - 30.
    God, who is an omnipotent, omniscient, and omnibenevolent Creator and Providence, exists and There is evil are logically compatible claims. God exists, If God exists, then He has a morally sufficient reason for allowing any evil that He does allow , and There is evil is a consistent triad of propositions. Thus any pair from that triad is also consistent. Thus God exists and There is evil are logically compatible. But this does not settle the question as to whether the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • The Freedom of God.Edward Wierenga - 2002 - Faith and Philosophy 19 (4):425-436.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  • A morally unsurpassable God must create the best.Erik J. Wielenberg - 2004 - Religious Studies 40 (1):43-62.
    I present a novel argument for the position that a morally unsurpassable God must create the best world that He has the power to create. I show that grace-based considerations of the sort proposed by Robert Adams neither refute my argument nor establish that a morally unsurpassable God need not create the best. I conclude with a discussion of the implications of my argument for the ‘no-best-world’ response to the problem of evil. (Published Online February 17 2004).
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • Rowe on God’s Freedom and God’s Grace.William J. Wainwright - 2005 - Philo 8 (1):12-22.
    Rowe argues that if for every good world there is a better, then God is not morally perfect since no matter what world God were to create he could have done better than he did. I contend that Rowe’s argument doesn’t do justice to the role grace plays in the theist’s doctrine of creation, and respond to five new criticisms of my position that Rowe offers in Can God be Free?
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Rowe on God’s Freedom and God’s Grace.William J. Wainwright - 2005 - Philo 8 (1):12-22.
    Rowe argues that if for every good world there is a better, then God is not morally perfect since no matter what world God were to create he could have done better than he did. I contend that Rowe’s argument doesn’t do justice to the role grace plays in the theist’s doctrine of creation, and respond to five new criticisms of my position that Rowe offers in Can God be Free?
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • 8. The Magnitude, Duration, and Distribution of Evil.Peter van Inwagen - 1988 - Philosophical Topics 16 (2):161-187.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   36 citations  
  • The Epistemology of Evil Possibilities.Paul Tidman - 1993 - Faith and Philosophy 10 (2):181-197.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • The epistemology of evil possibilities.Paul Tidman - 1993 - Faith and Philosophy 10 (2):181-197.
    In this paper I defend the Anselmian conception of God as a necessary being who is necessarily omnipotent, omniscient, and perfectly good against arguments that attempt to show that we have good reason to think there are evil possible worlds in which either God does not exist or in which He lacks at least one of these attributes. I argue that the critics of Anselmianism have failed to provide any compelling reason to think such worlds are possible. The best the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Robert Adams and the Best Possible World.Mark L. Thomas - 1996 - Faith and Philosophy 13 (2):252-259.
    Robert Merrihew Adams argues that it is permissible for a perfectly good moral agent to create a world less good than the best one she could create. He argues that God would exhibit the important virtue of grace in creating less than the best and that this virtue is incompatible with the merit considerations required by the standard of creating the best. In this paper I give three arguments for the compatibility of merit consideration and graciousness of God toward creation. (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Hume on miracles: Interpretation and criticism.James E. Taylor - 2007 - Philosophy Compass 2 (4):611–624.
    Philosophers continue to debate about David Hume’s case against the rationality of belief in miracles. This article clarifies semantic, epistemological, and metaphysical questions addressed in the controversy. It also explains the main premises of Hume’s argument and discusses criticisms of them. The article concludes that one’s evaluation of Hume’s argument will depend on one’s views about (a) the definitions of ’miracle’ and ’natural law’; (b) the type of reasoning one ought to employ to determine the probability that a particular miracle (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • God's problem of multiple choice.Lloyd Strickland - 2006 - Religious Studies 42 (2):141-157.
    A question that has been largely overlooked by philosophers of religion is how God would be able to effect a rational choice between two worlds of unsurpassable goodness. To answer this question, I draw a parallel with the paradigm cases of indifferent choice, including Buridan's ass, and argue that such cases can be satisfactorily resolved provided that the protagonists employ what Otto Neurath calls an ‘auxiliary motive’. I supply rational grounds for the employment of such a motive, and then argue (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Determining the best of all possible worlds.Lloyd Strickland - 2005 - Journal of Value Inquiry 39 (1):37-47.
    The concept of the best of all possible worlds is widely considered to be incoherent on the grounds that, for any world that might be termed the best, there is always another that is better. I note that underlying this argument is a conviction that the goodness of a world is determined by a single kind of good, the most plausible candidates for which are not maximizable. Against this I suggest that several goods may have to combine to determine the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Satisfied Pigs and Dissatisfied Philosophers: Schlesinger on the Problem of Evil.Stephen Graver - 1993 - Philosophical Investigations 16 (3):212-230.
    I argue that George Schlesinger's proposed solution to the problem of evil fails because: (1) the degree of desirability of state of a being is not properly regarded as a trade‐off between happiness on the one hand and potential on the other; (2) degree of desirability of state is not capable of infinite increase; (3) there is no hierarchy of possible beings, but at most an ordering of such beings in terms of preferences; (4) the idea of such a hierarchy (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • The Problem of No Best World.William L. Rowe - 1994 - Faith and Philosophy 11 (2):269-271.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Can God Be Free?William L. Rowe - 2002 - Faith and Philosophy 19 (4):405-424.
    Can God Be Free? is a penetrating study of a central problem in philosophy of religion: can it be right to regard God as free, and as praiseworthy for being perfectly good? Allowing that he has perfect knowledge and perfect goodness, if there is a best world for God to create he would have no choice other than to create it. But if God could not do otherwise than create the best world, he created the world of necessity, not freely, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   46 citations  
  • An atheistic argument from the improvability of the universe.R. K. Perkins - 1983 - Noûs 17 (2):239-250.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Essays in philosophical analysis.Nicholas Rescher - 1969 - [Pittsburgh]: University of Pittsburgh Press.
    This book presents twenty essays by philosopher Nicholas Rescher, representing more than a decade of his work.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Evil and a good God.Bruce R. Reichenbach - 1982 - New York: Fordham University Press.
    I argue that the atheological claim that the existence of pain and suffering either contradicts or makes improbable God's existence or his possession of certain critical properties cannot be sustained. The construction of a theodicy for both moral and natural evils is the focus of the central part of the book. In the final chapters I analyze the concept of the best possible world and the properties of goodness and omnipotence insofar as they are predicated of God.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  • How to Create a Physical Universe Ex Nihilo.Richard C. Potter - 1986 - Faith and Philosophy 3 (1):16-26.
    This paper examines the principle of creation ex nihilo as formulated by St. Augustine and contrasts it with the common-sense principle that “something cannot come from nothing.” It is argued that these two principles, if suitably interpreted, are logically consistent and a creation scenario is described in which their compatibility is demonstrated.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Warranted Christian Belief.P. Helm - 2001 - Mind 110 (440):1110-1115.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   157 citations  
  • Creation ex nihilo : Some considerations. [REVIEW]Thomas V. Morris - 1983 - International Journal for Philosophy of Religion 14 (4):233 - 239.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Must God Create?Sandra L. Menssen & Thomas D. Sullivan - 1995 - Faith and Philosophy 12 (3):321-341.
    In this paper we evaluate two sets of theistic arguments against the traditional position that Cod created with absolute freedom. The first set features several variations of Leibniz’s basic proof that Cod must create the best possible world. The arguments in the second set base the claim that Cod must create on the Platonic or Dionysian principle that goodness is essentially self-diffusive. We argue that neither the Leibnizian nor the Dionysian arguments are successful.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Freedom, human and divine.Tim Mawson - 2005 - Religious Studies 41 (1):55-69.
    In this paper I seek to show how God's freedom is not reduced or His power diminished by His inability to be less than perfectly good even though ours would be. That ours would be explains why it might prima facie appear to us that there is a ‘conceptual tension’ between some of the claims of traditional theism and reveals some interesting (well, to me anyway) differences between human freedom and divine freedom.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Evil and omnipotence.J. L. Mackie - 1955 - Mind 64 (254):200-212.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   202 citations  
  • Must God create the best?Michael Levine - 1996 - Sophia 35 (1):28-34.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • God and Infinite Hierarchies of Creatable Worlds.Bruce Langtry - 2006 - Faith and Philosophy 23 (4):460-476.
    This paper has been superseded by chapter 3 of my book "God, the Best, and Evil" (OUP 2008). The chapter concerns God's choices in cases in which God has infinitely many better and better options.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • God and the Best.Bruce Langtry - 1996 - Faith and Philosophy 13 (3):311-328.
    The paper reaches two main conclusions: Firstly, even if there are one or more possible worlds than which there are none better, God cannot actualise any of them. Secondly, if there are possible worlds which God can actualise, and than which God can actualise none better, then God must actualise one of them. The paper is neutral between compatibilist and libertarian views of creaturely freedom. The paper's main ideas have been used, with modifications, in my book "God, the Best, and (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Theistic Replies to the A Priori Argument for Atheism.Klaas J. Kraay - 2005 - Philo 8 (1):22-36.
    In the central chapter of Can God Be Free?, William Rowe offers what amounts to an a priori argument for atheism. In what follows, I first clarify this argument, and I then defend it against recent criticisms due to William Hasker. Next, however, I outline four ways in which theists might plausibly reply to Rowe’s argument.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • The Problem of No Best World.Klaas J. Kraay - 2010 - In Charles Taliaferro, Paul Draper & Philip L. Quinn (eds.), A Companion to Philosophy of Religion. Oxford, UK: Wiley‐Blackwell. pp. 482–490.
    This chapter contains sections titled: Background The Problem of No Best World Theistic Responses: Four Categories Works cited.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • The Real Problem of No Best World.Daniel Howard-Snyder & Frances Howard-Snyder - 1996 - Faith and Philosophy 13 (3):422-425.
    This is a reply to William Rowe, "The Problem of No Best World," Faith and Philosophy (1994).
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations