Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. Individuals: An Essay in Descriptive Metaphysics.James Cargile - 1959 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 38 (2):320-323.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   611 citations  
  • Counterfactuals.David Lewis - 1973 - Philosophy of Science 42 (3):341-344.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1140 citations  
  • Identity and substitutivity.Richard Cartwright - 1971 - In Milton Karl Munitz (ed.), Identity and individuation. New York,: New York University Press. pp. 119--133.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • Repeatable Artworks as Created Types.Lee Walters - 2013 - British Journal of Aesthetics 53 (4):461-477.
    I sketch here an intuitive picture of repeatable artworks as created types, which are individuated in part by historical paths (re)production. Although attractive, this view has been rejected by a number of authors on the basis of general claims about abstract objects. On consideration, however, these general claims are overgeneralizations, which whilst true of some abstracta, are not true of all abstract objects, and in particular, are not true of created types. The intuitive picture of repeatable artworks as created types (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   36 citations  
  • Critical Study Julian Dodd. Works of Music: An Essay in Ontology. (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2007).Gary Ostertag - 2012 - Noûs 46 (2):355-374.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Intrinsicality without naturalness.D. Gene Witmer, William Butchard & Kelly Trogdon - 2005 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 70 (2):326–350.
    Defense of an account of intrinsic properties in terms of (what is now called) grounding rather than naturalness.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   62 citations  
  • Artworks as historical individuals.Guy Rohrbaugh - 2003 - European Journal of Philosophy 11 (2):177–205.
    In 1907, Alfred Stieglitz took what was to become one of his signature photographs, The Steerage. Stieglitz stood at the rear of the ocean liner Kaiser Wilhelm II and photographed the decks, first-class passengers above and steerage passengers below, carefully exposing the film to their reflected light. Later, in the darkroom, Stieglitz developed this film and made a number of prints from the resulting negative. The photograph is a familiar one, an enduring piece of social commentary, but what exactly is (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   78 citations  
  • The metaphysics of properties.Alex Oliver - 1996 - Mind 105 (417):1-80.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   151 citations  
  • Quantitative parsimony.Daniel Nolan - 1997 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 48 (3):329-343.
    In this paper, I motivate the view that quantitative parsimony is a theoretical virtue: that is, we should be concerned not only to minimize the number of kinds of entities postulated by our theories (i. e. maximize qualitative parsimony), but we should also minimize the number of entities postulated which fall under those kinds. In order to motivate this view, I consider two cases from the history of science: the postulation of the neutrino and the proposal of Avogadro's hypothesis. I (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   121 citations  
  • Defining 'intrinsic'.Rae Langton & David Lewis - 1998 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 58 (2):333-345.
    Something could be round even if it were the only thing in the universe, unaccompanied by anything distinct from itself. Jaegwon Kim once suggested that we define an intrinsic property as one that can belong to something unaccompanied. Wrong: unaccompaniment itself is not intrinsic, yet it can belong to something unaccompanied. But there is a better Kim-style definition. Say that P is independent of accompaniment iff four different cases are possible: something accompanied may have P or lack P, something unaccompanied (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   205 citations  
  • Types, indicated and initiated.Robert Howell - 2002 - British Journal of Aesthetics 42 (2):105-127.
    I defend the conception of musical works as indicated temporally initiated types against Julian Dodd's recent argument that all types are eternal and uncreated. In doing so, I develop a new account of both cultural and natural types. While types are in a certain sense determined by the properties that underlie them, not all properties determine types; and properties such as being indicated by Beethoven exist only once the temporally initiated entities that those properties essentially involve exist. A cultural type (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   21 citations  
  • Defending musical perdurantism.Ben Caplan & Carl Matheson - 2006 - British Journal of Aesthetics 46 (1):59-69.
    If musical works are abstract objects, which cannot enter into causal relations, then how can we refer to musical works or know anything about them? Worse, how can any of our musical experiences be experiences of musical works? It would be nice to be able to sidestep these questions altogether. One way to do that would be to take musical works to be concrete objects. In this paper, we defend a theory according to which musical works are concrete objects. In (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   48 citations  
  • New Work For a Theory of Universals.David Lewis - 1997 - In David Hugh Mellor & Alex Oliver (eds.), Properties. New York: Oxford University Press.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1043 citations  
  • Works and Worlds of Art.George Dickie - 1983 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 44 (2):279-281.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Art and Its Objects.Jeffrey Wieand - 1981 - Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 40 (1):91-93.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   88 citations  
  • Modal Realism at Work.David Lewis - 1997 - In David Hugh Mellor & Alex Oliver (eds.), Properties. New York: Oxford University Press.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Objects and criteria of identity.E. J. Lowe - 1997 - In Bob Hale, Crispin Wright & Alexander Miller (eds.), A Companion to the Philosophy of Language. Chichester, West Sussex, UK: Wiley-Blackwell. pp. 990–1012.
    'Object' and 'criterion of identity' are philosophical terms of art whose application lies at a considerable theoretical remove from the surface phenomena of everyday linguistic usage. This partly explains their highly controversial status, for their point of application lies precisely where the concerns of linguists and philosophers of language merge with those of metaphysicians. This chapter explains the possession of determinate identity‐conditions. It argues that the distinction between 'abstract' and 'concrete' objects is itself a highly controversial one, and although it (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   33 citations  
  • Simple Generics.David Liebesman - 2011 - Noûs 45 (3):409-442.
    Consensus has it that generic sentences such as “Dogs bark” and “Birds fly” contain, at the level of logical form, an unpronounced generic operator: Gen. On this view, generics have a tripartite structure similar to overtly quantified sentences such as “Most dogs bark” and “Typically, birds fly”. I argue that Gen doesn’t exist and that generics have a simple bipartite structure on par with ordinary atomic sentences such as “Homer is drinking”. On my view, the subject terms of generics are (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   74 citations  
  • Intrinsic/extrinsic.I. L. Humberstone - 1996 - Synthese 108 (2):205-267.
    Several intrinsic/extrinsic distinctions amongst properties, current in the literature, are discussed and contrasted. The proponents of such distinctions tend to present them as competing, but it is suggested here that at least three of the relevant distinctions (including here that between non-relational and relational properties) arise out of separate perfectly legitimate intuitive considerations: though of course different proposed explications of the informal distinctions involved in any one case may well conflict. Special attention is paid to the question of whether a (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   92 citations  
  • Ockham's razor and the anti-superfluity principle.E. C. Barnes - 2000 - Erkenntnis 53 (3):353-374.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   26 citations  
  • Indeterminate identity, contingent identity and Abelardian predicates.Harold W. Noonan - 1991 - Philosophical Quarterly 41 (163):183-193.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   49 citations  
  • On concept and object.Gottlob Frege - 1951 - Mind 60 (238):168-180.
    Translation of Frege's 'Über Begriff und Gegenstand' (1892). Translation by Peter Geach, revised by Max Black.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   208 citations  
  • Psychophysical supervenience.Jaegwon Kim - 1982 - Philosophical Studies 41 (January):51-70.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   150 citations  
  • Types, Tokens, and Talk about Musical Works.Julian Dodd & Philip Letts - 2017 - Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 75 (3):249-263.
    It has recently been suggested that the type/token theorist concerning musical works cannot come up with an adequate semantic theory of those sentences in which we purport to talk about such works. Specifically, it has been claimed that, since types are abstract entities, a type/token theorist can only account for the truth of sentences such as “The 1812 Overture is very loud” and “Bach's Two Part Invention in C has an F-sharp in its fourth measure” by adopting an untenable semantic (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • The Interpretation of Frege's Philosophy.Michael Dummett - 1984 - Philosophical Quarterly 34 (136):402-414.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   145 citations  
  • Universals: An Opinionated Introduction.Jerrold Levinson & D. M. Armstrong - 1992 - Philosophical Review 101 (3):654.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   174 citations  
  • The Interpretation of Frege's Philosophy. [REVIEW]Tyler Burge - 1984 - Philosophical Review 93 (3):454-458.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   61 citations  
  • 'By Leibniz's law': Remarks on a fallacy.By Benjamin Schnieder - 2006 - Philosophical Quarterly 56 (222):39–54.
    The article is an investigation of a certain form of argument that refers to Leibniz’s Law as its inference ticket (where Leibniz’s Law is understood as the thesis that if x=y.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  • Against musical works as eternal types.Saam Trivedi - 2002 - British Journal of Aesthetics 42 (1):73-82.
    I criticize Julian Dodd's Platonist conception of musical works as discovered eternal types, and defend and elaborate upon Jerrold Levinson's conception of musical works as creatable indicated types. I raise broadly three sorts of worries for Dodd. First, I argue that Dodd conflates types with Platonist universals in claiming that types are eternal and discovered. Secondly, I raise worries for Dodd's Platonist claim that musical works are discovered not created. Here I argue that Dodd's claim goes against our current musical (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • Science without Numbers.Michael D. Resnik - 1983 - Noûs 17 (3):514-519.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   164 citations  
  • Four ontologies.Eddy M. Zemach - 1970 - Journal of Philosophy 67 (8):231-247.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   39 citations  
  • Inquiry.Jon Barwise - 1986 - Philosophical Review 95 (3):429.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   282 citations  
  • Works and Worlds of Art.Peter Lewis - 1982 - Philosophical Quarterly 32 (127):185-186.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • Types and Tokens.Linda Wetzel - 2014 - In Edward N. Zalta (ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Stanford, CA: The Metaphysics Research Lab.
    The distinction between a type and its tokens is auseful metaphysical distinction. In §1 it is explained what itis, and what it is not. Its importance and wide applicability inlinguistics, philosophy, science and everyday life are brieflysurveyed in §2. Whether types are universals is discussed in§3. §4 discusses some other suggestions for what types are,both generally and specifically. Is a type the sets of its tokens?What exactly is a word, a symphony, a species? §5 asks what atoken is. §6 considers (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   59 citations  
  • Talk about Music: From Wolterstorffian Ambiguity to Generics.Stefano Predelli - 2011 - Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 69 (3):273-283.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Works of Music: An Essay in Ontology.Julian Dodd - 2008 - Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 66 (2):201-203.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   77 citations