Switch to: Citations

References in:

Who Is Afraid of Numbers?

Utilitas 20 (4):447-461 (2008)

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. Mortal Questions.[author unknown] - 1979 - Tijdschrift Voor Filosofie 43 (3):578-578.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   519 citations  
  • A Theory of Justice: Original Edition.John Rawls - 2009 - Belknap Press.
    Though the revised edition of A Theory of Justice, published in 1999, is the definitive statement of Rawls's view, so much of the extensive literature on Rawls's theory refers to the first edition. This reissue makes the first edition once again available for scholars and serious students of Rawls's work.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3482 citations  
  • What we owe to each other.Thomas Scanlon - 1998 - Cambridge: Belknap Press of Harvard University Press.
    In this book, T. M. Scanlon offers new answers to these questions, as they apply to the central part of morality that concerns what we owe to each other.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2452 citations  
  • A theory of justice.John Rawls - unknown
    Though the revised edition of A Theory of Justice, published in 1999, is the definitive statement of Rawls's view, so much of the extensive literature on Rawls's theory refers to the first edition.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4066 citations  
  • Can a Nonconsequentialist Count Lives?Alan Strudler David Wasserman - 2003 - Philosophy and Public Affairs 31 (1):71-94.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  • Selecting people randomly.John Broome - 1984 - Ethics 95 (1):38-55.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   61 citations  
  • Let them Eat Chances: Probability and Distributive Justice.David Wasserman - 1996 - Economics and Philosophy 12 (1):29-49.
    Jon Elster reports that in 1940, and again in 1970, the U.S. draft lottery was challenged for falling short of the legally mandated ‘random selection’. On both occasions, the physical mixing of the lots appeared to be incomplete, since the birth dates were clustered in a way that would have been extremely unlikely if the lots were fully mixed. There appears to have been no suspicion on either occasion that the deficiency in the mixing was intended, known, or believed to (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   30 citations  
  • Can a Nonconsequentialist Count Lives?David Wasserman & Alan Strudler - 2003 - Philosophy and Public Affairs 31 (1):71-94.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   25 citations  
  • The individualist lottery: How people count, but not their numbers.Jens Timmermann - 2004 - Analysis 64 (2):106–112.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   28 citations  
  • The individualist lottery: how people count, but not their numbers.J. Timmermann - 2004 - Analysis 64 (2):106-112.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   49 citations  
  • Inequality.Andrew Moore - 1995 - Philosophical Quarterly 45 (178):114-115.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   31 citations  
  • Inequality.Jan Narveson - 1996 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 56 (2):482-486.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   37 citations  
  • Replies.T. M. Scanlon - 2002 - Social Theory and Practice 28 (2):337-358.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   31 citations  
  • Replies.T. M. Scanlon - 2003 - Ratio 16 (4):424–439.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   30 citations  
  • Replies.Thomas Scanlon - 2002 - Ratio 16 (4):424-439.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  • Reasons and Persons.Joseph Margolis - 1986 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 47 (2):311-327.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1638 citations  
  • Justifiability to each person.Derek Parfit - 2003 - Ratio 16 (4):368–390.
    sonable, in this sense, if we ignore, or give too little weight to, some other people's well-being or moral claims.' Some critics have suggested that, because Scanlon appeals to this sense of 'reasonable', his formula is empty. On this objection, whenever we believe that some act is wrong, we shall believe that people have moral claims not to be treated in this way. We could therefore argue that such acts are disallowed by some principle which no one could reasonably reject, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   71 citations  
  • Scanlon and the claims of the many versus the one.Michael Otsuka - 2000 - Analysis 60 (3):288-293.
    In "What We Owe to Each Other", T. M. Scanlon argues that one should save the greater number when faced with the choice between saving one life and two or more different lives. It is, Scanlon claims, a virtue of this argument that it does not appeal to the claims of groups of individuals but only to the claims of individuals. I demonstrate that this argument for saving the greater number, indeed, depends, contrary to what Scanlon says, upon an appeal (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   48 citations  
  • How to be consistent without saving the greater number.Kirsten Meyer - 2006 - Philosophy and Public Affairs 34 (2):136–146.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Fairness in life and Death Cases.Gerald Lang - 2005 - Erkenntnis 62 (3):321-351.
    John Taurek famously argued that, in ‘conflict cases’, where we are confronted with a smaller and a larger group of individuals, and can choose which group to save from harm, we should toss a coin, rather than saving the larger group. This is primarily because coin-tossing is fairer: it ensures that each individual, regardless of the group to which he or she belongs, has an equal chance of being saved. This article provides a new response to Taurek’s argument. It proposes (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Contractualism on saving the many.R. Kumar - 2001 - Analysis 61 (2):165-170.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   47 citations  
  • Precis of Morality, Mortality, Vol. 1: Death and Whom to Save from ItMorality, Mortality, Vol. 1: Death and Whom to Save from It. [REVIEW]Frances Kamm - 1998 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 58 (4):939.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Morality, Mortality, Vol. 1: Death and Whom to Save from It.Frances Kamm - 1998 - Philosophical and Phenomenological Research 58 (4):963-967.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   36 citations  
  • Aggregation and two moral methods.F. M. Kamm - 2005 - Utilitas 17 (1):1-23.
    I begin by reconsidering the arguments of John Taurek and Elizabeth Anscombe on whether the number of people we can help counts morally. I then consider arguments that numbers should count given by F. M. Kamm and Thomas Scanlon, and criticism of them by Michael Otsuka. I examine how different conceptions of the moral method known as pairwise comparison are at work in these different arguments and what the ideas of balancing and tie-breaking signify for decision-making in various types of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   21 citations  
  • Saving the greater number without combining claims.I. Hirose - 2001 - Analysis 61 (4):341-342.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   30 citations  
  • Aggregation and numbers.Iwao Hirose - 2004 - Utilitas 16 (1):62-79.
    This article considers the reach of arguments for saving the greater number without interpersonal aggregation, and argues that interpersonal aggregation is useful to encompass the proper respect due to each separate person. I first give a precise definition of interpersonal aggregation, which many non-utilitarians try to avoid. Then, I show that consequentialism and Scanlon can justify the case for the greater number without interpersonal aggregation. However, I propose the Aggregation Approach, which justifies the case for the greater number in some (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   22 citations  
  • Aggregation and Numbers.Iawo Hirose - 2004 - Utilitas 16 (1):62-79.
    This article considers the reach of arguments for saving the greater number without interpersonal aggregation, and argues that interpersonal aggregation is useful to encompass the proper respect due to each separate person. I first give a precise definition of interpersonal aggregation, which many non-utilitarians try to avoid. Then, I show that consequentialism and Scanlon can justify the case for the greater number without interpersonal aggregation. However, I propose the Aggregation Approach, which justifies the case for the greater number in some (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   20 citations  
  • Weighing Goods: Equality, Uncertainty and Time.John Broome - 1991 - Wiley-Blackwell.
    This study uses techniques from economics to illuminate fundamental questions in ethics, particularly in the foundations of utilitarianism. Topics considered include the nature of teleological ethics, the foundations of decision theory, the value of equality and the moral significance of a person's continuing identity through time.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   456 citations  
  • Anarchy, State, and Utopia.Robert Nozick - 1974 - Philosophy 52 (199):102-105.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1991 citations  
  • Should the numbers count?John Taurek - 1977 - Philosophy and Public Affairs 6 (4):293-316.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   250 citations  
  • Saving the Greatest Number.Thom Brooks - 2002 - Logique Et Analyse 45 (177-178):55-59.
    Imagine there are three boats equidistant from one another. You are alone in the first boat. The other two boats are sinking fast: one boat has one person (A), the other has two persons (B&C). There is only enough time to allow saving either A or B&C before their boats sink, drowning whoever is onboard. Will we always combine claims of those wishing to be saved and rescue B&C? Otsuka says that the 'Kamm-Scanlon' contractualist framework that does not aggregating various (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Mortal Questions.Thomas Nagel - 1983 - Religious Studies 19 (1):96-99.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   460 citations  
  • Inequality.Larry Temkin - 1995 - Ethics 105 (3):663-665.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   125 citations  
  • The Morality of Freedom.Joseph Raz - 1986 - Philosophy 63 (243):119-122.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1015 citations