Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. (3 other versions)Tractatus logico-philosophicus.Ludwig Wittgenstein - 1922 - Filosoficky Casopis 52:336-341.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1913 citations  
  • A Merleau-Pontyian Critique of Husserl’s and Searle’s Representationalist Accounts of Action.Hubert L. Dreyfus - 2000 - Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 100 (3):287-302.
    Husserl and Searle agree that, for a bodily movement to be an action, it must be caused by a propositional representation. Husserl's representation is a mental state whose intentional content is what the agent is trying to do; Searle thinks of the representation as a logical structure expressing the action's conditions of satisfaction. Merleau-Ponty criticises both views by introducing a kind of activity he calls motor intentionality, in which the agent, rather than aiming at success, feels drawn to reduce a (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  • (2 other versions)Critique of Pure Reason.I. Kant - 1787/1998 - Philosophy 59 (230):555-557.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1924 citations  
  • Knowing How.Jason Stanley & Timothy Willlamson - 2001 - Journal of Philosophy 98 (8):411-444.
    Many philosophers believe that there is a fundamental distinction between knowing that something is the case and knowing how to do something. According to Gilbert Ryle, to whom the insight is credited, knowledge-how is an ability, which is in turn a complex of dispositions. Knowledge-that, on the other hand, is not an ability, or anything similar. Rather, knowledge-that is a relation between a thinker and a true proposition.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   496 citations  
  • (2 other versions)Mind and World.Huw Price & John McDowell - 1994 - Philosophical Books 38 (3):169-181.
    How do rational minds make contact with the world? The empiricist tradition sees a gap between mind and world, and takes sensory experience, fallible as it is, to provide our only bridge across that gap. In its crudest form, for example, the traditional idea is that our minds consult an inner realm of sensory experience, which provides us with evidence about the nature of external reality. Notoriously, however, it turns out to be far from clear that there is any viable (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1048 citations  
  • Coping with Things-in-themselves: A Practice-Based Phenomenological Argument for Realism.Hubert L. Dreyfus & Charles Spinosa - 1999 - Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 42 (1):49-78.
    Against Davidsonian (or deflationary) realism, it is argued that it is coherent to believe that science can in principle give us access to the functional components of the universe as they are in themselves in distinction from how they appear to us on the basis of our quotidian concerns or sensory capacities. The first section presents the deflationary realist's argument against independence. The second section then shows that, although Heidegger pioneered the deflationary realist account of the everyday, he sought to (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   26 citations  
  • (2 other versions)Critique of pure reason.Immanuel Kant - 2007 - In Elizabeth Schmidt Radcliffe, Richard McCarty, Fritz Allhoff & Anand Vaidya (eds.), Late modern philosophy: essential readings with commentary. Oxford: Wiley-Blackwell. pp. 449-451.
    One of the cornerstone books of Western philosophy, Critique of Pure Reason is Kant's seminal treatise, where he seeks to define the nature of reason itself and builds his own unique system of philosophical thought with an approach known as transcendental idealism. He argues that human knowledge is limited by the capacity for perception and attempts a logical designation of two varieties of knowledge: a posteriori, the knowledge acquired through experience; and a priori, knowledge not derived through experience. This accurate (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   958 citations  
  • The enchantment of words: Wittgenstein's Tractatus logico-philosophicus.Denis McManus - 2006 - New York: Oxford University Press.
    The Enchantment of Words is a study of Wittgenstein's early masterpiece, the Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus. Recent years have seen a great revival of interest in the Tractatus. McManus's study of the work offers novel readings of all its major themes and sheds light on issues in metaphysics, ethics and the philosophies of mind, language, and logic.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • Mind, Value, and Reality.John Henry McDowell - 1998 - Cambridge: Harvard University Press.
    Written over the last two decades, John McDowell's papers, as a whole, deal with issues of philosophy. Specifically, separate groups of essays look at the ethical writings of Aristotle and Plato; moral questions regarding the Greek tradition; interpretations of Wittgenstein's work; and, finally, questions about personal identity and the character of first-person thought and speech.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   274 citations  
  • Getting Heidegger off the west coast.Carleton B. Christensen - 1998 - Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 41 (1):65 – 87.
    According to Hubert L. Dreyfus, Heidegger's central innovation is his rejection of the idea that intentional activity and directedness is always and only a matter of having representational mental states. This paper examines the central passages to which Dreyfus appeals in order to motivate this claim. It shows that Dreyfus misconstrues these passages significantly and that he has no grounds for reading Heidegger as anticipating contemporary anti-representationalism in the philosophy of mind. The misunderstanding derives from lack of sensitivity to Heidegger's (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   22 citations  
  • (1 other version)Objective content.Miller Alexander - 2003 - Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 77 (1):73–90.
    [Alan Weir] This paper addresses the problem of how to account for objective content-for the distinction between how we actually apply terms and the conditions in which we ought to apply them-from within a naturalistic framework. Though behaviourist or dispositionalist approaches are generally held to be unsuccessful in naturalising objective content or 'normativity', I attempt to restore the credibility of such approaches by sketching a behaviouristic programme for explicating objective content. /// [Alexander Miller] Paul Boghossian (1989, 1990) has argued, on (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • (2 other versions)Philosophy of Mind.Jaegwon Kim - 1996 - [Boulder, Colo.]: Westview Press.
    The philosophy of mind has always been a staple of the philosophy curriculum. But it has never held a more important place than it does today, with both traditional problems and new topics often sparked by the developments in the psychological, cognitive, and computer sciences. Jaegwon Kim’s Philosophy of Mind is the classic, comprehensive survey of the subject. Now in its second edition, Kim explores, maps, and interprets this complex and exciting terrain. Designed as an introduction to the field for (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   63 citations  
  • (1 other version)Mind and World.John Henry McDowell - 1994 - Cambridge: Harvard University Press.
    Much as we would like to conceive empirical thought as rationally grounded in experience, pitfalls await anyone who tries to articulate this position, and ...
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1020 citations  
  • Making It Explicit: Reasoning, Representing, and Discursive Commitment.Robert Brandom - 1994 - Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press.
    What would something unlike us--a chimpanzee, say, or a computer--have to be able to do to qualify as a possible knower, like us? To answer this question at the very heart of our sense of ourselves, philosophers have long focused on intentionality and have looked to language as a key to this condition. Making It Explicit is an investigation into the nature of language--the social practices that distinguish us as rational, logical creatures--that revises the very terms of this inquiry. Where (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   997 citations  
  • Meaning and intentionality in Wittgenstein's later philosophy.John McDowell - 1992 - Midwest Studies in Philosophy 17 (1):40-52.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   46 citations  
  • (4 other versions)Philosophical investigations.Ludwig Wittgenstein & G. E. M. Anscombe - 1953 - Revue Philosophique de la France Et de l'Etranger 161:124-124.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3159 citations  
  • Another Plea for Modesty.John McDowell - 1997 - In Richard G. Heck (ed.), Language, thought, and logic: essays in honour of Michael Dummett. New York: Oxford University Press.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  • Transcendental Heidegger.Steven Galt Crowell & Jeff Malpas (eds.) - 2007 - Stanford, Calif.: Stanford University Press.
    The thirteen essays in this volume represent the most sustained investigation, in any language, of the connections between Heidegger's thought and the tradition of transcendental philosophy inaugurated by Kant. This collection examines Heidegger's stand on central themes of transcendental philosophy: subjectivity, judgment, intentionality, truth, practice, and idealism. Several essays in the volume also explore hitherto hidden connections between Heidegger's later "post-metaphysical" thinking—where he develops a "topological" approach that draws as much upon poetry as upon the philosophical tradition—and the transcendental project (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   28 citations  
  • (1 other version)The primacy of phenomenology over logical analysis: A critique of Searle.Hubert L. Dreyfus - 1999 - Philosophical Topics 27 (2):3-24.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   20 citations  
  • (1 other version)Philosophy of Mind.Jaegwon Kim - 1996 - Philosophy 72 (280):317-320.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   110 citations  
  • Précis of M aking It Explicit: Reasoning, Representing, and Discursive Commitment.Robert Brandom & Robert B. Brandom - 1997 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 57 (1):153.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   210 citations  
  • Does "belief holism" show that reductive dispositionalism about content could not be true?Alexander Miller - 2003 - Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 77 (1):73-90.
    Paul Boghossian has argued, on grounds concerning the holistic nature of belief fixation, that there are principled reasons for thinking that 'optimal conditions' versions of reductive dispositionalism about content cannot hope to satisfy a condition of extensional accuracy. I discern three separable strands of argument in Boghossian's work—the circularity objection, the open-endedness objection, and the certification objection—and argue that each of these objections fails. My conclusion is that for all that Boghossian has shown, 'optimal conditions' versions of reductive dispositionalism have (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • The nature of natural norms: Why selected functions are systemic capacity functions.Paul Sheldon Davies - 2000 - Noûs 34 (1):85–107.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   20 citations  
  • Subjectivity: Locating the first-person in being and time.Steven Crowell - 2001 - Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 44 (4):433 – 454.
    It is often held that, in contrast to Husserl, Heidegger's account of intentionality makes no essential reference to the first- person stance. This paper argues, on the contrary, that an account of the first- person, or 'subjectivity', is crucial to Heidegger's account of intelligibility and so of the intentionality, or 'aboutness' of our acts and thoughts, that rests upon it. It first offers an argument as to why the account of intelligibility in Division I of Being and Time, based on (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   23 citations  
  • Limits of phenomenology.John R. Searle - 2000 - In Mark A. Wrathall & Jeff Malpas (eds.), Heidegger, Coping, and Cognitive Science. MIT Press.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Heidegger and artificial intelligence.Beth Preston - 1993 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 53 (1):43-69.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Practices, practical holism, and background practices.David G. Stern - 2000 - In Mark Wrathall & Jeff Malpas (eds.), Heidegger, Coping, and Cognitive Science: Essays in Honor of Hubert L. Dreyfus, Volume 2. MIT Press.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • (3 other versions)Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus.Ludwig Wittgenstein - 2023 - Nordic Wittgenstein Review 11.
    Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus by Ludwig Wittgenstein: three parallel tree-structured editions. (1) Tree-structured arrangement of the German text, edited by David G. Stern, Joachim Schulte and Katia Saporiti. (2) Tree-structured arrangement of the English translation by Ogden and Ramsey, edited by David G. Stern. (3) Tree-structured arrangement of the English translation by Pears and McGuinness, edited by David G. Stern.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   332 citations  
  • Conscience and reason: Heidegger and the grounds of intentionality.Steven Crowell - 2007 - In Steven Galt Crowell & Jeff Malpas (eds.), Transcendental Heidegger. Stanford, Calif.: Stanford University Press. pp. 43--62.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   24 citations  
  • Heidegger's Method: Philosophical Concepts as Formal Indications.Daniel O. Dahlstrom - 1994 - Review of Metaphysics 47 (4):775 - 795.
    In 1929, after rejecting the suggestion that contemporary Christians may be expected to feel "threatened" by Kierkegaard's criticisms, the Protestant theologian Gerhardt Kuhlmann remarks.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   40 citations  
  • Heidegger, measurement and the 'intelligibility' of science.Denis McManus - 2007 - European Journal of Philosophy 15 (1):82–105.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Boghossian, Miller and Lewis on dispositional theories of meaning.Denis McManus - 2000 - Mind and Language 15 (4):393-399.
    Paul Boghossian has pointed out a ’circularity problem’ for dispositionalist theories of meaning: as a result of the holistic character of belief fixation, one cannot identify someone’s meaning such and such with facts of the form S is disposed to utter P under conditions C, without C involving the semantic and intentional notions that such a theory was to explain. Alex Miller has recently suggested an ’ultra‐sophisticated dispositionalism’ (modelled on David Lewis’s well known version of functionlism) and has argued that (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • The Enchantment of Words: Wittgenstein's Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus.Denis Mcmanus - 2007 - Philosophy 82 (322):657-661.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • (1 other version)The Primacy of Phenomenology over Logical Analysis.Hubert L. Dreyfus - 1999 - Philosophical Topics 27 (2):3-24.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   22 citations  
  • Boghossian on Reductive Dispositionalism About Content: The Case Strengthened.Alexander Miller - 1997 - Mind and Language 12 (1):1-10.
    Paul Boghossian has recently argued against reductive dispositionalism concerning mental content. However, there is a powerful version of reductive dispositionalism—based on work by Ramsey and Lewis—that Boghossian does not consider. In this paper I argue that Boghossian's arguments can be adapted to apply even to this stronger version of reductionism.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • (1 other version)Review: The New Wittgenstein. [REVIEW]D. McManus - 2005 - Mind 114 (453):129-137.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • (1 other version)Objective Content.Alexander Miller - 2003 - Supplement to the Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 77 (1):73-90.
    Paul Boghossian has argued, on grounds concerning the holistic nature of belief fixation, that there are principled reasons for thinking that 'optimal conditions' versions of reductive dispositionalism about content cannot hope to satisfy a condition of extensional accuracy. I discern three separable strands of argument in Boghossian's work—the circularity objection, the open-endedness objection, and the certification objection—and argue that each of these objections fails. My conclusion is that for all that Boghossian has shown, 'optimal conditions' versions of reductive dispositionalism have (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations