Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. Kant on Intuition in Geometry.Emily Carson - 1997 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 27 (4):489 - 512.
    It's well-known that Kant believed that intuition was central to an account of mathematical knowledge. What that role is and how Kant argues for it are, however, still open to debate. There are, broadly speaking, two tendencies in interpreting Kant's account of intuition in mathematics, each emphasizing different aspects of Kant's general doctrine of intuition. On one view, most recently put forward by Michael Friedman, this central role for intuition is a direct result of the limitations of the syllogistic logic (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   45 citations  
  • Kant on the method of mathematics.Emily Carson - 1999 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 37 (4):629-652.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Kant on the Method of MathematicsEmily Carson1. INTRODUCTIONThis paper will touch on three very general but closely related questions about Kant’s philosophy. First, on the role of mathematics as a paradigm of knowledge in the development of Kant’s Critical philosophy; second, on the nature of Kant’s opposition to his Leibnizean predecessors and its role in the development of the Critical philosophy; and finally, on the specific role of intuition (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   35 citations  
  • Space as Form of Intuition and as Formal Intuition: On the Note to B160 in Kant's Critique of Pure Reason.Christian Onof & Dennis Schulting - 2015 - Philosophical Review 124 (1):1-58.
    In his argument for the possibility of knowledge of spatial objects, in the Transcendental Deduction of the B-version of the Critique of Pure Reason, Kant makes a crucial distinction between space as “form of intuition” and space as “formal intuition.” The traditional interpretation regards the distinction between the two notions as reflecting a distinction between indeterminate space and determinations of space by the understanding, respectively. By contrast, a recent influential reading has argued that the two notions can be fused into (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   34 citations  
  • (4 other versions)Kant's gesammelte Schriften.[author unknown] - 1905 - Revue Philosophique de la France Et de l'Etranger 60:110-110.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   87 citations  
  • Critique of the Power of Judgment.Hannah Ginsborg, Immanuel Kant, Paul Guyer & Eric Matthews - 2002 - Philosophical Review 111 (3):429.
    This new translation is an extremely welcome addition to the continuing Cambridge Edition of Kant’s works. English-speaking readers of the third Critique have long been hampered by the lack of an adequate translation of this important and difficult work. James Creed Meredith’s much-reprinted translation has charm and elegance, but it is often too loose to be useful for scholarly purposes. Moreover it does not include the first version of Kant’s introduction, the so-called “First Introduction,” which is now recognized as indispensable (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   404 citations  
  • Kant and the Exact Sciences.William Harper & Michael Friedman - 1995 - Philosophical Review 104 (4):587.
    This is a very important book. It has already become required reading for researchers on the relation between the exact sciences and Kant’s philosophy. The main theme is that Kant’s continuing program to find a metaphysics that could provide a foundation for the science of his day is of crucial importance to understanding the development of his philosophical thought from its earliest precritical beginnings in the thesis of 1747, right through the highwater years of the critical philosophy, to his last (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   91 citations  
  • In A. Janiak.I. Newton - 2004 - In Margaret A. Simons, Marybeth Timmermann & Mary Beth Mader (eds.), Philosophical Writings. University of Illinois Press.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   33 citations  
  • Kant on Sensibility and the Understanding in the 1770s.Alison Laywine - 2003 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 33 (4):443 - 482.
    The Duisburg Nachlaß is a bundle of Kant’s handwritten notes. These notes almost certainly go back to some time in 1775. Though very obscure, they replay issues in Kant’s early metaphysics just as clearly as they anticipate issues in the Critique of Pure Reason. This makes them an important way-station in Kant’s philosophical development—all the more important, because he published nothing in the 1770s and left no other extended writings in his own hand. A proper understanding of the Duisburg Nachlaß (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Kant's Stance on the Relationalist-Substantivalist Debate and Its Justification.James Messina - 2018 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 56 (4):697-726.
    kant famously claims that space is merely a feature of the mind—something subjective—rather than a mind-independent feature of reality in itself.1 In accepting the subjectivity thesis, Kant rejects the transcendental realist assumption that he thinks has traditionally, albeit tacitly, been made in debates about the nature of space. According to this assumption, space has to do with things in themselves. For the Newtonians, as Kant understands their position, space is a substance-like thing in itself; for the Leibnizians, space consists in (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Kant.Paul Guyer - 2007 - Tijdschrift Voor Filosofie 69 (4):767-767.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   159 citations  
  • Critique of Pure Reason.Wolfgang Schwarz - 1966 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 26 (3):449-451.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   683 citations  
  • Kant on conic sections.Alison Laywine - 2014 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 44 (5-6):719-758.
    This paper tries to make sense of Kant's scattered remarks about conic sections to see what light they shed on his philosophy of mathematics. It proceeds by confronting his remarks with the source that seems to have informed his thinking about conic sections: the Conica of Apollonius. The paper raises questions about Kant's attitude towards mathematics and the way he understood the cognitive resources available to us to do mathematics.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Critique of pure reason.Günter Zöller - 2002 - Philosophical Review 111 (1):113-116.
    This new translation of the first Critique forms part of a fifteen-volume English-language edition of the works of Immanuel Kant under the general editorship of this volume’s editor-translators, Paul Guyer and Allen Wood. The edition, which is almost complete by now, comprises all of Kant’s published works along with extensive selections from his literary remains, his correspondence, and student transcripts of his lecture courses in metaphysics, ethics, logic, and anthropology. The Cambridge edition aims at a consistent English rendition of Kant’s (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   82 citations  
  • The difference between original, metaphysical, and geometrical representations of space.Clinton Tolley - 2016 - In Dennis Schulting (ed.), Kantian Nonconceptualism. London, England: Palgrave. pp. 257-285.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Kant, Kästner and the Distinction between Metaphysical and Geometric Space.Christian Onof & Dennis Schulting - 2014 - Kantian Review 19 (2):285-304.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  • (1 other version)Kant’s Theory of Science.Gordon Nagel - 1979 - Philosophy of Science 46 (4):654-655.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • Kant on the Unity of Space and the Synthetic Unity of Apperception.James Messina - 2014 - Kant Studien 105 (1):5-40.
    In the Transcendental Aesthetic, Kant famously characterizes space as a unity, understood as an essentially singular whole. He further develops his account of the unity of space in the B-Deduction, where he relates the unity of space to the original synthetic unity of apperception, and draws an infamous distinction between form of intuition and formal intuition. Kant ’s cryptic remarks in this part of the Critique have given rise to two widespread and diametrically opposed readings, which I call the Synthesis (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   28 citations  
  • The relationship between space and mutual interaction: Kant contra Newton and Leibniz.James Messina - 2017 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 47 (1):43-65.
    Kant claims that we cannot cognize the mutual interaction of substances without their being in space; he also claims that we cannot cognize a ‘spatial community’ among substances without their being in mutual interaction. I situate these theses in their historical context and consider Kant’s reasons for accepting them. I argue that they rest on commitments regarding the metaphysical grounding of, first, the possibility of mutual interaction among substances-as-appearances and, second, the actuality of specific distance-relations among such substances. By illuminating (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Kant's Theory of Science.Gordon G. Brittan - 2015 - Princeton University Press.
    While interest in Kant's philosophy has increased in recent years, very little of it has focused on his theory of science. This book gives a general account of that theory, of its motives and implications, and of the way it brought forth a new conception of the nature of philosophical thought. To reconstruct Kant's theory of science, the author identifies unifying themes of his philosophy of mathematics and philosophy of physics, both undergirded by his distinctive logical doctrines, and shows how (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   21 citations  
  • Theoretical Philosophy, 1755-1770.Immanuel Kant, David Walford, Ralf Meerbote & J. Michael Young - 1995 - Erkenntnis 43 (3):405-410.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   52 citations  
  • Theoretical Philosophy, 1755-1770.Frederick C. Beiser, Immanuel Kant, David Walford & Ralf Meerbote - 1995 - Philosophical Review 104 (2):277.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   52 citations