Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. The Last Word.Simon Blackburn & Thomas Nagel - 1998 - Philosophical Review 107 (4):653.
    Like all of Nagel's work, this is a book with a message: an apparently clear, simple message, forcefully presented and repeated. The message is that there is a limit to the extent to which we can "get outside" fundamental forms of thought, including logical, mathematical, scientific, and ethical thought. "Getting outside" means taking up a biological or psychological or sociological or economic or political view of ourselves as thinkers. It also inclines many people to talk of the contingency or subjectivity (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   68 citations  
  • Mathematical truth.Paul Benacerraf - 1973 - Journal of Philosophy 70 (19):661-679.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   686 citations  
  • What makes induction rational?David Malet Armstrong - 1991 - Dialogue 30 (4):503-11.
    In this paper I put forward what I think is a new approach to the problem of induction. I sketched the approach in brief sections of a book published in 1983. The same idea had occurred to the English philosopher John Foster and he presented it in a paper at about the same time.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  • Divine necessity.Robert Merrihew Adams - 1983 - Journal of Philosophy 80 (11):741-752.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   32 citations  
  • Wittgenstein on following a rule.John McDowell - 1984 - Synthese 58 (March):325-364.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   244 citations  
  • Inventing Logical Necessity.Crispin Wright - 1986 - In Jeremy Butterfield (ed.), Language, mind and logic. New York: Cambridge University Press.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   43 citations  
  • Wittgenstein on the Foundations of Mathematics.Cora Diamond - 1981 - Philosophical Quarterly 31 (125):352-366.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  • The nature of laws.Michael Tooley - 1977 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 7 (4):667-98.
    This paper is concerned with the question of the truth conditions of nomological statements. My fundamental thesis is that it is possible to set out an acceptable, noncircular account of the truth conditions of laws and nomological statements if and only if relations among universals - that is, among properties and relations, construed realistically - are taken as the truth-makers for such statements. My discussion will be restricted to strictly universal, nonstatistical laws. The reason for this limitation is not that (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   399 citations  
  • Thought experiments and the epistemology of laws.Roy A. Sorensen - 1992 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 22 (1):15-44.
    The aim of this paper is to show how thought experiments help us learn about laws. After providing examples of this kind of nomic illumination in the first section, I canvass explanations of our modal knowledge and opt for an evolutionary account. The basic application is that the laws of nature have led us to develop rough and ready intuitions of physical possibility which are then exploited by thought experimenters to reveal some of the very laws responsible for those intuitions. (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   81 citations  
  • Review: Peacocke on Modality. [REVIEW]Gideon Rosen - 2002 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 64 (3):641 - 648.
    We know a great deal about what is possible, so modal knowledge must be possible, not just in principle but by ordinary methods. Christopher Peacocke’s leading thought in Chapter 4 of Being Known is that this fact places significant constraints on philosophical treatments of modality. Modal realism is ruled out on the ground that it renders modal truth “radically inaccessible”, and actualism is forced upon us. It goes without saying that any account of the modal facts must eventually dovetail with (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Peacocke on Modality.Gideon Rosen - 2002 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 64 (3):641-648.
    We know a great deal about what is possible, so modal knowledge must be possible, not just in principle but by ordinary methods. Christopher Peacocke’s leading thought in Chapter 4 of Being Known is that this fact places significant constraints on philosophical treatments of modality. Modal realism is ruled out on the ground that it renders modal truth “radically inaccessible”, and actualism is forced upon us. It goes without saying that any account of the modal facts must eventually dovetail with (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Précis of Being Known_ _*[REVIEW]Christopher Peacocke - 2002 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 64 (3):636-640.
    The topic of Being Known is what I call the Integration Challenge, which is the challenge of providing, for any given domain, a simultaneously acceptable metaphysics and epistemology for that domain. In virtually every domain of thought, it is a substantive task to reconcile our metaphysics and our epistemology of that domain. In some cases, we have an intuitively acceptable metaphysics, but cannot find a plausible epistemology which would allow us knowledge of truths for which that is the right metaphysics. (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Précis of Being Known_ _*.Christopher Peacocke - 2002 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 64 (3):636-640.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   165 citations  
  • Being known.Christopher Peacocke - 1999 - New York: Oxford University Press.
    Being Known is a response to a philosophical challenge which arises for every area of thought: to reconcile a plausible account of what is involved in the truth of statements in a given area with a credible account of how we can know those statements. Christopher Peacocke presents a framework for addressing the challenge, a framework which links both the theory of knowledge and the theory of truth with the theory of concept-possession.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   238 citations  
  • The epistemology of possible worlds: A guided tour.John O'Leary-Hawthorne - 1996 - Philosophical Studies 84 (2-3):183 - 202.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • The Disappearing 'We'.Jonathan Lear & Barry Stroud - 1984 - Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 58 (1):219 - 258.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   36 citations  
  • What's Really Wrong with Constructive Empiricism? Van Fraassen and the Metaphysics of Modality.Jac Ladyman - 2000 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 51 (4):837-856.
    Constructive empiricism is supposed to offer a positive alternative to scientific realism that dispenses with the need for metaphysics. I first review the terms of the debate before arguing that the standard objections to constructive empiricism are not decisive. I then explain van Fraassen's views on modality and counterfactuals, and argue that, because constructive empiricism recommends on epistemological grounds belief in the empirical adequacy rather than the truth of theories, it requires that there be an objective modal distinction between the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   49 citations  
  • What's really wrong with constructive empiricism? Van Fraassen and the metaphysics of modality.James Ladyman - 2000 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 51 (4):837-856.
    Constructive empiricism is supposed to offer a positive alternative to scientific realism that dispenses with the need for metaphysics. I first review the terms of the debate before arguing that the standard objections to constructive empiricism are not decisive. I then explain van Fraassen's views on modality and counterfactuals, and argue that, because constructive empiricism recommends on epistemological grounds belief in the empirical adequacy rather than the truth of theories, it requires that there be an objective modal distinction between the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   57 citations  
  • Ontology and realism about modality.Crawford L. Elder - 1999 - Australasian Journal of Philosophy 77 (3):292 – 302.
    To be a realist about modality, need one claim that more exists than just the various objects and properties that populate the world—e.g. worlds other than the actual one, or maximal consistent sets of propositions? Or does the existence of objects and properties by itself involve the obtaining of necessities (and possibilities) in re? The latter position is now unpopular but not unfamiliar. Aristotle held that objects have essences, and hence necessarily have certain properties. Recently it has been argued that (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • An epistemological defence of realism about necessity.Crawford L. Elder - 1992 - Philosophical Quarterly 42 (168):317-336.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • Kant.Ralph Charles Sutherland Walker - 1997 - New York: Routledge.
    "First Published in 1999, Routledge is an imprint of Taylor & Francis, an informa company.".
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   47 citations  
  • The Bounds of Sense.P. F. Strawson - 1966 - Philosophy 42 (162):379-382.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   376 citations