Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. When Is Birth Unfair to the Child?Bonnie Steinbock & Ron McClamrock - 1994 - Hastings Center Report 24 (6):15-21.
    Is it wrong to bring children who will have serious diseases and disabilities into the world? In particular, is it unfair to them? The notion that existence itself can be an injury is the basis for a recent new tort known as "wrongful life" (Steinbock, 1986). This paper considers Feinberg's theory of harm as the basis for a claim of wrongful life, and concludes that rarely can the stringent conditions imposed by his analysis be met. Another basis for maintaining that (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   47 citations  
  • (1 other version)Use of assisted reproductive technology to reduce the risk of transmission of HIV in discordant couples wishing to have their own children where the male partner is seropositive with an undetectable viral load: Table 1.H. W. G. Baker, A. Mijch, S. Garland, S. Crowe, M. Dunne, D. Edgar, G. Clarke, P. Foster & J. Blood - 2003 - Journal of Medical Ethics 29 (6):315-320.
    The advances in treatment of HIV and the introduction of polymerase chain reaction assay for the virus now make it acceptable for HIV discordant couples where the male partner is seropositive to attempt to conceive through artificial insemination by husband (AIH) or via in vitro fertilisation. With undetectable viral load and washed sperm, there is minimal risk of transmission of HIV to the female partner, children, other patients, or staff. We describe the development of a programme of AIH for HIV (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • (1 other version)Use of assisted reproductive technology to reduce the risk of transmission of HIV in discordant couples wishing to have their own children where the male partner is seropositive with an undetectable viral load.H. W. G. Baker - 2003 - Journal of Medical Ethics 29 (6):315-320.
    The advances in treatment of HIV and the introduction of polymerase chain reaction assay for the virus now make it acceptable for HIV discordant couples where the male partner is seropositive to attempt to conceive through artificial insemination by husband or via in vitro fertilisation. With undetectable viral load and washed sperm, there is minimal risk of transmission of HIV to the female partner, children, other patients, or staff. We describe the development of a programme of AIH for HIV discordant (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Fatherless families: How important is genetic relatedness?Giuliana Fuscaldo - 2002 - Monash Bioethics Review 21 (3):18-29.
    How should families be constructed? Does it matter if we choose to ignore ‘blood ties’ and raise children without their genetic parents? The debate over a recent court ruling allowing single and lesbian women access to assisted reproductive technologies (ART’s) illustrates two possible answers to this question. Many of those opposed to the ruling argue that the traditional biological family is the natural family unit and the ideal family form, which should be preserved. Amongst those in favour it is argued (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Prenatal genetic testing and discrimination against the disabled: A conceptual analysis.Ani B. Satz - 1999 - Monash Bioethics Review 18 (4):11-22.
    This article examines the conceptual claim that prenatal genetic testing, given the option to abort disabled fetuses, discriminates against the disabled. The claim is examined in the context of both external quality of life judgments and women’s competing interests in and right to reproductive freedom. The conceptual claim to discrimination fails in both contexts if moral standing is not attributed to the fetus.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Ethical implications of women’s underrepresentation in clinical trials.Merle Spriggs - 1999 - Monash Bioethics Review 18 (2):S11-S20.
    Excluding women from participating in clinical drug trials might seem like a good thing. It may seem like a good way to protect women from the risks of being a research subject and a way to prevent fetal harm. However, the exclusion or inadequate representation of women in clinical trials may actually cause harm. Excluding women from clinical trials does not rule out the possibility of damage to offspring. Nor does it guarantee researchers or institutions freedom from legal liability. The (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations