Switch to: Citations

References in:

Experimental Philosophy: 1935-1965

In Tania Lombrozo, Joshua Knobe & Shaun Nichols (eds.), Oxford Studies in Experimental Philosophy, Volume 1. Oxford University Press. pp. vol. 1, pp. 325-368 (2014)

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. The fight against revelation in semantical studies.Herman Tönnessen - 1949 - Synthese 8 (1):225.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • The fight against revelation in semantical studies.Herman Tönnessen - 1949 - Synthese 8 (1):225 - 234.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Vindication of the humpty dumpty attitude towards language.Herman Tennesen - 1960 - Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 3 (1-4):185 – 198.
    Effective objective (sachlich) verbal communication is dependent upon the use of linguistic locutions which are: a) suitable for some special purposes, b) clear ( i.e ., having a satsifactorily high degree of subsumability), and c) in accordance with some ordinary (i.e. , frequently occurring) language usages. Only in so far as point c is concerned is a study of actual language usage of (indirect) value to philosophers. And this holds true regardless of whether one's underlying assumption tends towards the view: (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Whereof one has been silent, thereof one may have to speak.Herman Tennessen - 1961 - Journal of Philosophy 58 (10):263-274.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • What should we say?Herman Tennessen - 1959 - Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 2 (1-4):265 – 290.
    Preliminary summaries of a few empirio?semantical investigations1 concerning such sentences as: can we say x, should we ever (ordinarily) say x, x is self?evident (tautological, contradictory, nonsensical), P does not know what be is talking about, x is voluntary (involuntary) and: that is no excuse.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Ordinary language in memoriam.Herman Tennessen - 1965 - Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 8 (1-4):225 – 248.
    Taking as a point of departure a recently published collection of representative contributions from various philosophers who claim to ?proceed from ordinary language?, this article examines ordinary language philosophy in the light of some of the claims made by these philosophers. The claims are criticized mainly for failing to account for the variability of the use of terms in respect both of depth of intention and special contexts. These factors are such as to render the claims in question false when (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • On worthwhile hypotheses.Herman Tennessen - 1959 - Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 2 (1-4):183 – 198.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Logical oddities and locutional scarcities.Herman Tennessen - 1959 - Synthese 11 (4):369 - 388.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Evidence and illustration.Herman Tennessen - 1959 - Synthese 11 (3):274 - 276.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • The semantic conception of truth and the foundations of semantics.Alfred Tarski - 1943 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 4 (3):341-376.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   544 citations  
  • Linguistic Reductionism and the Idea of ‘Potential Meaning’.K. Stern - 1969 - The Monist 53 (2):246-261.
    It is, by now, a common-place, to point out that contemporary philosophy under the influence of Moore and Wittgenstein is concerned with language rather than with the ‘world’ There is, no doubt, a great deal of room to niggle at this rather broad characterization of recent philosophy, but anyone familiar with recent philosophical history in Britain and America will agree that such a generalization is as true as such generalizations can be. Thus, J. J. C. Smart points out that.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Arne Naess — Dogmas and Problems of Empiricism.Friedrich Stadler - 2010 - Vienna Circle Institute Yearbook 14:11-31.
    Arne Dekke Eide Naess was born on January 27, 1912 in Oslo. After a long and successful life he passed away on January 12, 2009 in Oslo as the most renowned Norwegian philosopher, where he was honoured with a state funeral. He was one of the most important public figures in Norway and in his later years became known all over the world as a pioneer of the ecological movement. Given this publicity in recent decades his earlier life was forgotten (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Process vagueness.Roy A. Sorensen - 1990 - Linguistics and Philosophy 13 (5):589 - 618.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Psychologism.Elliott Sober - 1978 - Journal for the Theory of Social Behaviour 8 (July):165-91.
    The end of the nineteenth century is remembered as a time when psychology freed itself from philosophy and carved out an autonomous subject matter for itself. In fact, this time of emancipation was also a time of exile: while the psychologists were leaving, philosophers were slamming the door behind them. Frege is celebrated for having demonstrated the irrelevance of psychological considerations to philosophy. Some of Frege’s reasons for distinguishing psychological questions from philosophical ones were sound, but one of Frege’s most (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   77 citations  
  • Epistemology and the new way of words.Wilfred Sellars - 1947 - Journal of Philosophy 44 (24):645-660.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • Epistemology and the New Way of Words.Wilfrid Sellars - 1948 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 13 (4):222-223.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Ordinary language.Gilbert Ryle - 1953 - Philosophical Review 62 (2):167-186.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   45 citations  
  • Counter-intuitivity and the method of analysis.Richard Rudner - 1950 - Philosophical Studies 1 (6):83 - 89.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Objectivity of norms and value-judgments according to recent scandinavian philosophy.Harald Ofstad - 1951 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 12 (1):42-68.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • The descriptive definition of the concept 'legal norm' proposed by Hans Kelsen: An elementary analytical and critical investigation.Harald Ofstad - 1950 - Theoria 16 (2):118-151.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Morality, choice and inwardness.Harald Ofstad - 1965 - Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 8 (1-4):33 – 73.
    The present paper tries to analyse the way in which Judge William, in Sören Kierkegaard's work Either/Or, distinguishes between the aesthetic and the ethical way of life. Basically his distinctions seem to be that the ethicist is a seriously committed person (has inwardness) whereas the aestheticist is indifferent, and that the former accepts universal rules whereas the latter makes an exception for himself. ? In order to come from the aesthetic to the ethical stage one must, according to Judge William, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Philosophy and Logical Syntax. [REVIEW]E. N. & Rudolf Carnap - 1935 - Journal of Philosophy 32 (13):357.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   115 citations  
  • Common-sense And Truth.Arne Ness - 1938 - Theoria 4 (1):39-58.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   28 citations  
  • The Inquiring Mind.Arne Naess - 1961 - Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 4:162.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Psychological research and Humean problems.Siri Naess & Arne Naess - 1960 - Philosophy of Science 27 (2):134-146.
    In this article the question is raised whether philosophers, studying Humean problems, might profit from the empirical findings of contemporary psychology. A text from Hume's Treatise of Human Nature is analyzed in an attempt to find out (1) whether his problems are open to empirical testing. Each sentence in the text is classified into normative, declarative, analytic and synthetic. A prevalence of declarative, synthetic sentences is found. Further, the question is examined (2) whether contemporary empirical psychology has contributed to the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Synonymity as revealed by intuition.Arne Naess - 1957 - Philosophical Review 66 (1):87-93.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Toward a theory of interpretation and preciseness.Arne Naess - 1949 - Theoria 15 (1-3):220-241.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • Logical equivalence, intentional isomorphism and synonymity as studied by questionnaires.Arne Naess - 1956 - Synthese 10 (1):471 - 479.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Logical Empiricism and the Uniqueness of the Schlick Seminar: A Personal Experience with Consequences.Arne Naess - 1993 - Vienna Circle Institute Yearbook 1:11-25.
    In what follows I shall speak about many phenomena, but what I wish to convey more than anything else is a combination of positive aspects of the rightly famous seminar headed by Moritz Schlick the years before he was shot on the stairs of the University of Vienna in 1936. These aspects make the seminar unique. I have taken part in a wealth of good seminars before and after 1936, but my experience as a participant of that seminar makes it, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Do we know that basic norms cannot be true or false?Arne Naess - 1959 - Theoria 25 (1):31-53.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Husserl on the apodictic evidence of ideal laws.Arne Naess - 1977 - In Jitendranath Mohanty (ed.), Readings on Edmund Husserl's Logical investigations. The Hague: M. Nijhoff. pp. 67--75.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • A study of 'or'.Arne Naess - 1961 - Synthese 13 (1):49 - 60.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Philosophy of science and science of philosophy.Charles W. Morris - 1935 - Philosophy of Science 2 (3):271-286.
    It is proposed to examine the consequences which ensue if philosophy is deliberately oriented around the methods and results of science. That such reorientation has been more or less unconsciously taking place for centuries is evident; the problem demands particular discussion at this time only because the reorientation has gone so far and with such success as to challenge seriously certain past conceptions of philosophy and to demand of philosophers what, if anything, is left for them to do. For present (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Democracy in a World of Tensions.Richard Mckeon - 1952 - Philosophy East and West 2 (1):86-88.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Language and the use of language.Max Wright - 1967 - Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 10 (1-4):439-446.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • On the verification of statements about ordinary language.Benson Mates - 1964 - Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 1 (1-4):161 – 171.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   29 citations  
  • An experimental philosophy manifesto.Joshua Knobe & Shaun Nichols - 2008 - In Joshua Michael Knobe & Shaun Nichols (eds.), Experimental Philosophy. Oxford: Oxford University Press. pp. 3--14.
    It used to be a commonplace that the discipline of philosophy was deeply concerned with questions about the human condition. Philosophers thought about human beings and how their minds worked. They took an interest in reason and passion, culture and innate ideas, the origins of people’s moral and religious beliefs. On this traditional conception, it wasn’t particularly important to keep philosophy clearly distinct from psychology, history, or political science. Philosophers were concerned, in a very general way, with questions about how..
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   123 citations  
  • The folk concept of intentional action: Philosophical and experimental issues.Edouard Machery - 2008 - Mind and Language 23 (2):165–189.
    Recent experimental fi ndings by Knobe and others ( Knobe, 2003; Nadelhoffer, 2006b; Nichols and Ulatowski, 2007 ) have been at the center of a controversy about the nature of the folk concept of intentional action. I argue that the signifi cance of these fi ndings has been overstated. My discussion is two-pronged. First, I contend that barring a consensual theory of conceptual competence, the signifi cance of these experimental fi ndings for the nature of the concept of intentional action (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   95 citations  
  • The Structure of Physical Laws.Ludvig Lövestad - 1945 - Theoria 11 (1):40-70.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Ideal Language Philosophy and Experiments on Intuitions.Sebastian Lutz - 2009 - Studia Philosophica Estonica 2 (2):117-139.
    Proponents of linguistic philosophy hold that all non-empirical philosophical problems can be solved by either analyzing ordinary language or developing an ideal one. I review the debates on linguistic philosophy and between ordinary and ideal language philosophy. Using arguments from these debates, I argue that the results of experimental philosophy on intuitions support linguistic philosophy. Within linguistic philosophy, these experimental results support and complement ideal language philosophy. I argue further that some of the critiques of experimental philosophy are in fact (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Definition and hypothesis in Plato'smeno(II).Laura Grimm - 1964 - Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 7 (1-4):227-230.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Psychologism: a case study in the sociology of philosophical knowledge.Martin Kusch - 1995 - New York: Routledge.
    In the 1890's, when fields such as psychology and philosophy were just emerging, turf wars between the disciplines were common-place. Philosophers widely discounted the possibility that psychology's claim to empirical truth had anything relevant to offer their field. And psychologists, such as the crazed and eccentric Otto Weinegger, often considered themselves philosophers. Freud, it is held, was deeply influenced by his wife, Martha's, uncle, who was also a philosopher. The tension between the fields persisted, until the two fields eventually matured (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   63 citations  
  • Experimental Philosophy.Joshua Knobe, Wesley Buckwalter, Shaun Nichols, Philip Robbins, Hagop Sarkissian & Tamler Sommers - 2012 - Annual Review of Psychology 63 (1):81-99.
    Experimental philosophy is a new interdisciplinary field that uses methods normally associated with psychology to investigate questions normally associated with philosophy. The present review focuses on research in experimental philosophy on four central questions. First, why is it that people's moral judgments appear to influence their intuitions about seemingly nonmoral questions? Second, do people think that moral questions have objective answers, or do they see morality as fundamentally relative? Third, do people believe in free will, and do they see free (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   128 citations  
  • Experimental philosophy and philosophical significance.Joshua Knobe - 2007 - Philosophical Explorations 10 (2):119 – 121.
    Kauppinen argues that experimental philosophy cannot help us to address questions about the semantics of our concepts and that it therefore has little to contribute to the discipline of philosophy. This argument raises fascinating questions in the philosophy of language, but it is simply a red herring in the present context. Most researchers in experimental philosophy were not trying to resolve semantic questions in the first place. Their aim was rather to address a more traditional sort of question, the sort (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   32 citations  
  • The rise and fall of experimental philosophy.Antti Kauppinen - 2007 - Philosophical Explorations 10 (2):95 – 118.
    In disputes about conceptual analysis, each side typically appeals to pre-theoretical 'intuitions' about particular cases. Recently, many naturalistically oriented philosophers have suggested that these appeals should be understood as empirical hypotheses about what people would say when presented with descriptions of situations, and have consequently conducted surveys on non-specialists. I argue that this philosophical research programme, a key branch of what is known as 'experimental philosophy', rests on mistaken assumptions about the relation between people's concepts and their linguistic behaviour. The (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   208 citations  
  • Contextual Implication.Isabel C. Hungerland - 1970 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 35 (3):458-458.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Contextual implication.Isabel C. Hungerland - 1960 - Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 3 (1-4):211 – 258.
    In this essay, I have rejected the inductive interpretation of the paradigm of contextual implication (to say “p”; is to imply that one believes that ) and proposed in its stead an explicatory model according to which a speaker in making a statement contextually implies whatever one is entitled to infer on the basis of the presumption that his act of stating is normal. In developing this model, I show how contextual implication depends on three distinct matters: a stating context, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • Was Arne Naess Recognized as the Founder of Deep Ecology Prematurely? Semantics and Environmental Philosophy.Benjamin Howe - 2010 - Environmental Ethics 32 (4):369-383.
    According to Arne Naess, his environmental philosophy is influenced by the philosophy of language called empirical semantics, which he first developed in the 1930s as a participant in the seminars of the Vienna Circle. While no one denies his claim, most of his commentators defend views about his environmental philosophy that contradict the tenets of his semantics. In particular, they argue that he holds that deep ecology’s supporters share a world view, and that the movement’s platform articulates shared principles. Naess, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • The Emperor’s New Intuitions.Jaakko Hintikka - 1999 - Journal of Philosophy 96 (3):127-147.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   74 citations  
  • Depth of intention.Ingemund Gullvåg - 1983 - Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 26 (1):31 – 83.
    The paper attempts to reconstruct some notions of Naess's semantics, and at the same time to relate them to more recent developments. On Naess's view, there is no such thing as a language in the sense of a shared structure which determines clear-cut literal meanings like Fregean Gedanken or propositions. We use words, and try to interpret each other; but there is no a priori or intuitive basis for secure and precise knowledge about language. Interpretation or understanding, as well as (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations