Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. The Logic of Conditional Negation.John Cantwell - 2008 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 49 (3):245-260.
    It is argued that the "inner" negation $\mathord{\sim}$ familiar from 3-valued logic can be interpreted as a form of "conditional" negation: $\mathord{\sim}$ is read '$A$ is false if it has a truth value'. It is argued that this reading squares well with a particular 3-valued interpretation of a conditional that in the literature has been seen as a serious candidate for capturing the truth conditions of the natural language indicative conditional (e.g., "If Jim went to the party he had a (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   29 citations  
  • A Routley-Meyer affixing style semantics for logics containing Aristotle's Thesis.Ross T. Brady - 1989 - Studia Logica 48 (2):235-241.
    We provide a semantics for relevant logics with addition of Aristotle's Thesis, ∼(A→∼A) and also Boethius,(A→B)→∼(A→∼B). We adopt the Routley-Meyer affixing style of semantics but include in the model structures a regulatory structure for all interpretations of formulae, with a view to obtaining a lessad hoc semantics than those previously given for such logics. Soundness and completeness are proved, and in the completeness proof, a new corollary to the Priming Lemma is introduced (c.f.Relevant Logics and their Rivals I, Ridgeview, 1982).
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • A propositional logic with subjunctive conditionals.R. B. Angell - 1962 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 27 (3):327-343.
    In this paper a formalized logic of propositions, PA1, is presented. It is proven consistent and its relationships to traditional logic, to PM ([15]), to subjunctive (including contrary-to-fact) implication and to the “paradoxes” of material and strict implication are developed. Apart from any intrinsic merit it possesses, its chief significance lies in demonstrating the feasibility of a general logic containing theprinciple of subjunctive contrariety, i.e., the principle that ‘Ifpwere true thenqwould be true’ and ‘Ifpwere true thenqwould be false’ are incompatible.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   51 citations  
  • A Propositional Logic with Subjunctive Conditionals.R. B. Angell - 1970 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 35 (3):464-465.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  • Connexive Modal Logic.H. Wansing - 1998 - In Marcus Kracht, Maarten de Rijke, Heinrich Wansing & Michael Zakharyaschev (eds.), Advances in Modal Logic. CSLI Publications. pp. 367-383.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   27 citations  
  • Two Objections to System CC1 of Connexive Implication.John Woods - 1968 - Dialogue 7 (3):473-475.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • A Note On Negation In Categorial Grammar.Heinrich Wansing - 2007 - Logic Journal of the IGPL 15 (3):271-286.
    A version of strong negation is introduced into Categorial Grammar. The resulting syntactic calculi turn out to be systems of connexive logic.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • Semantics for connexive logics. I.Richard Routley - 1978 - Studia Logica 37 (4):393 - 412.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  • On systems containing Aristotle's thesis.R. Routley & H. Montgomery - 1968 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 33 (1):82-96.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  • Dialogical connexive logic.Shahid Rahman & Helge Rückert - 2001 - Synthese 127 (1-2):105-139.
    Many of the discussions about conditionals can best be put as follows:can those conditionals that involve an entailment relation be formulatedwithin a formal system? The reasons for the failure of the classical approachto entailment have usually been that they ignore the meaning connectionbetween antecedent and consequent in a valid entailment. One of the firsttheories in the history of logic about meaning connection resulted from thestoic discussions on tightening the relation between the If- and the Then-parts of conditionals, which in this (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • Dialogical Connexive Logic.Shahid Rahman & Helge Rückert - 2001 - Synthese 127 (1-2):105-139.
    Many of the discussions about conditionals can best be put as follows:can those conditionals that involve an entailment relation be formulatedwithin a formal system? The reasons for the failure of the classical approachto entailment have usually been that they ignore the meaning connectionbetween antecedent and consequent in a valid entailment. One of the firsttheories in the history of logic about meaning connection resulted from thestoic discussions on tightening the relation between the If- and the Then-parts of conditionals, which in this (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Negation as cancellation, and connexive logic.Graham Priest - 1999 - Topoi 18 (2):141-148.
    Of the various accounts of negation that have been offered by logicians in the history of Western logic, that of negation as cancellation is a very distinctive one, quite different from the explosive accounts of modern "classical" and intuitionist logics, and from the accounts offered in standard relevant and paraconsistent logics. Despite its ancient origin, however, a precise understanding of the notion is still wanting. The first half of this paper offers one. Both conceptually and historically, the account of negation (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   49 citations  
  • Aristotle's Thesis between paraconsistency and modalization.Claudio Pizzi - 2005 - Journal of Applied Logic 3 (1):119-131.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Boethius' thesis and conditional logic.Claudio Pizzi - 1977 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 6 (1):283 - 302.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • Experiments on Aristotle’s Thesis.Niki Pfeifer - 2012 - The Monist 95 (2):223-240.
    Two experiments (N1 = 141, N2 = 40) investigate two versions of Aristotle’s Thesis for the first time. Aristotle’s Thesis is a negated conditional, which consists of one propositional variable with a negation either in the antecedent (version 1) or in the consequent (version 2). This task allows us to infer if people interpret indicative conditionals as material conditionals or as conditional events. In the first experiment I investigate between-participants the two versions of Aristotle’s Thesis crossed with abstract versus concrete (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   29 citations  
  • 40 years of FDE: An Introductory Overview.Hitoshi Omori & Heinrich Wansing - 2017 - Studia Logica 105 (6):1021-1049.
    In this introduction to the special issue “40 years of FDE”, we offer an overview of the field and put the papers included in the special issue into perspective. More specifically, we first present various semantics and proof systems for FDE, and then survey some expansions of FDE by adding various operators starting with constants. We then turn to unary and binary connectives, which are classified in a systematic manner. First-order FDE is also briefly revisited, and we conclude by listing (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   48 citations  
  • On contra-classical variants of Nelson logic n4 and its classical extension.Hitoshi Omori & Heinrich Wansing - 2018 - Review of Symbolic Logic 11 (4):805-820.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Generalizing Functional Completeness in Belnap-Dunn Logic.Hitoshi Omori & Katsuhiko Sano - 2015 - Studia Logica 103 (5):883-917.
    One of the problems we face in many-valued logic is the difficulty of capturing the intuitive meaning of the connectives introduced through truth tables. At the same time, however, some logics have nice ways to capture the intended meaning of connectives easily, such as four-valued logic studied by Belnap and Dunn. Inspired by Dunn’s discovery, we first describe a mechanical procedure, in expansions of Belnap-Dunn logic, to obtain truth conditions in terms of the behavior of the Truth and the False, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   21 citations  
  • Intensional relations.Everett J. Nelson - 1930 - Mind 39 (156):440-453.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   41 citations  
  • Aristotle's thesis in consistent and inconsistent logics.Chris Mortensen - 1984 - Studia Logica 43 (1-2):107 - 116.
    A typical theorem of conaexive logics is Aristotle''s Thesis(A), (AA).A cannot be added to classical logic without producing a trivial (Post-inconsistent) logic, so connexive logics typically give up one or more of the classical properties of conjunction, e.g.(A & B)A, and are thereby able to achieve not only nontriviality, but also (negation) consistency. To date, semantical modellings forA have been unintuitive. One task of this paper is to give a more intuitive modelling forA in consistent logics. In addition, while inconsistent (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  • Connexive Gentzen.S. McCall - 2014 - Logic Journal of the IGPL 22 (6):964-981.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Connexive implication.Storrs Mccall - 1966 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 31 (3):415-433.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   68 citations  
  • Connexive implication and the syllogism.Storrs McCall - 1967 - Mind 76 (303):346-356.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  • Strong Connexivity.Andreas Kapsner - 2012 - Thought: A Journal of Philosophy 1 (2):141-145.
    Connexive logics aim to capture important logical intuitions, intuitions that can be traced back to antiquity. However, the requirements that are imposed on connexive logic are actually not enough to do justice to these intuitions, as I will argue. I will suggest how these demands should be strengthened.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • Contra-classical logics.Lloyd Humberstone - 2000 - Australasian Journal of Philosophy 78 (4):438 – 474.
    Only propositional logics are at issue here. Such a logic is contra-classical in a superficial sense if it is not a sublogic of classical logic, and in a deeper sense, if there is no way of translating its connectives, the result of which translation gives a sublogic of classical logic. After some motivating examples, we investigate the incidence of contra-classicality (in the deeper sense) in various logical frameworks. In Sections 3 and 4 we will encounter, originally as an example of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   38 citations  
  • Connexive logic.Heinrich Wansing - 2008 - Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   49 citations  
  • Negation And Contradiction.Richard Routley Val Routley, Richard Sylvan & Richard Routley - 1985 - Revista Columbiana de Mathematicas:201 - 231.
    The problems of the meaning and function of negation are disentangled from ontological issues with which they have been long entangled. The question of the function of negation is the crucial issue separating relevant and paraconsistent logics from classical theories. The function is illuminated by considering the inferential role of contradictions, contradiction being parasitic on negation. Three basic modelings emerge: a cancellation model, which leads towards connexivism, an explosion model, appropriate to classical and intuitionistic theories, and a constraint model, which (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations