Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. Ideality, sub-ideality and deontic logic.Andrew J. I. Jones & Ingmar Pörn - 1985 - Synthese 65 (2):275 - 290.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   47 citations  
  • Deontic logic.G. H. von Wright - 1951 - Mind 60 (237):1-15.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   166 citations  
  • I. deontic logic.G. H. von Wright - 1951 - Mind 60 (237):1-15.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   175 citations  
  • A note on the deontic system DL of Jones and pörn.Sven Ove Hansson - 1989 - Synthese 80 (3):427 - 428.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Logical and analytic truths that are not necessary.Edward N. Zalta - 1988 - Journal of Philosophy 85 (2):57-74.
    The author describes an interpreted modal language and produces some clear examples of logical and analytic truths that are not necessary. These examples: (a) are far simpler than the ones cited in the literature, (b) show that a popular conception of logical truth in modal languages is incorrect, and (c) show that there are contingent truths knowable ``a priori'' that do not depend on fixing the reference of a term.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   43 citations  
  • A reduction of deontic logic to alethic modal logic.Alan Ross Anderson - 1958 - Mind 67 (265):100-103.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   55 citations  
  • Relative necessity.Timothy Smiley - 1963 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 28 (2):113-134.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   38 citations  
  • Formal Logic.A. N. Prior - 1964 - Studia Logica 15:298-301.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   63 citations  
  • Necessity and Relative Contingency.Claudio Pizzi - 2007 - Studia Logica 85 (3):395-410.
    The paper introduces a contingential language extended with a propositional constant τ axiomatized in a system named KΔτ , which receives a semantical analysis via relational models. A definition of the necessity operator in terms of Δ and τ allows proving (i) that KΔτ is equivalent to a modal system named K□τ (ii) that both KΔτ and K□τ are tableau-decidable and complete with respect to the defined relational semantics (iii) that the modal τ -free fragment of KΔτ is exactly the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • The Logic of Norms.Alan Ross Anderson - 1958 - Logique Et Analyse 1 (2):84.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Obligation and modal logic.Hector-Neri Castañeda - 1960 - Logique Et Analyse 3 (4):40-48.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Metaphysical Necessity and Modal Logics.Philip L. Quinn - 1982 - The Monist 65 (4):444-455.
    Metaphysics, as I understand it, is the attempt to construct theories which give correct accounts in general terms of pervasive structural features of reality. Though not precise and not intended as an explicit definition, this characterization is comprehensive enough to include both descriptive and revisionary varieties of metaphysical theory. The enterprise of descriptive metaphysics, Strawson tells us, consists in describing “the actual structure of our thought about the world.” Presumably a philosopher would favor this approach to metaphysics if he or (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Norms and Values.Sven Ove Hansson - 1991 - Critica 23 (67):3-13.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • The iteration of deontic modalities.L. F. Goble - 1966 - Logique Et Analyse 9:197-209.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations