Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. The 'scandal' of cartesian interactionism.Robert C. Richardson - 1982 - Mind 91 (January):20-37.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   22 citations  
  • Descartes' Metaphysical Physics.Daniel GARBER - 1992 - Studia Leibnitiana 26 (1):127-128.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   99 citations  
  • (4 other versions)Naming and Necessity.Saul Kripke - 1980 - Philosophy 56 (217):431-433.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1734 citations  
  • Descartes on time and causality.J. E. K. Secada - 1990 - Philosophical Review 99 (1):45-72.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • Creation and conservation once more.William Lane Craig - 1998 - Religious Studies 34 (2):177-188.
    God is conceived in the Western theistic tradition to be both the Creator and Conservor of the universe. These two roles were typically classed as different aspects of creation, originating creation and continuing creation. On pain of incoherence, however, conservation needs to be distinguished from creation. Contrary to current analyses (such as Philip Quinn's), creation should be explicated in terms of God's bringing something into being, while conservation should be understood in terms of God's preservation of something over an interval (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • Descartes and occasionalism.Daniel Garber - 1989 - In Steven Nadler (ed.), Causation in Early Modern Philosophy: Cartesianism, Occasionalism, and Preestablished Harmony. Pennsylvania State University Press. pp. 9--26.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   20 citations  
  • The Battle of the Gods and Giants: The Legacies of Descartes and Gassendi, 1655-1715.Thomas M. Lennon - 1993 - Princeton University Press.
    These paperback editions preserve the original texts of these important books while presenting them in durable paperback editions.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  • Malebranche: A Study of a Cartesian System.James M. Humber - 1979 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 40 (2):299-300.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • (2 other versions)The Search after Truth.Nicholas Malebranche, Thomas M. Lennon & Paul J. Olscamp - 1982 - Philosophy of Science 49 (1):146-147.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   123 citations  
  • Divine Conservation and Spinozistic Pantheism.Philip L. Quinn - 1979 - Religious Studies 15 (3):289 - 302.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Descartes's Nomic Concurrentism: Finite Causation and Divine Concurrence.Andrew Pessin - 2003 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 41 (1):25-49.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Journal of the History of Philosophy 41.1 (2003) 25-49 [Access article in PDF] Descartes's Nomic Concurrentism:Finite Causation and Divine Concurrence Andrew Pessin DESCARTES APPEARS TO HOLD the traditional view that God acts in the world via willing. 1 In recent papers on his successor Malebranche, who also holds that view, I have argued that since volitions are paradigm representational states, close attention to the representational content of God's volitions (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Mind-body interaction and metaphysical consistency: A defense of Descartes.Eileen O'Neill - 1987 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 25 (2):227-245.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   20 citations  
  • The ontological status of Malebranchean ideas.Monte Cook - 1998 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 36 (4):525-544.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:The Ontological Status of Malebranchean IdeasMonte CookOnce again... we are brought back to a fundamental problem in Malebranche’s theory of ideas. What is the ontological status or nature of ideas? They are neither substances nor modifications of any substance. Yet in the Cartesian schema these are the only alternatives: something is either a substance or a modification of a substance. And Malebranche, however modified his Cartesianism, is at least (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Classical Theism and Pantheism: a Victory for Process Theism?: ROBERT A. OAKES.Robert A. Oakes - 1977 - Religious Studies 13 (2):167-173.
    In Anselm's Discovery , Professor Hartshorne makes the rather startling and counterintuitive claim that ‘…there is indeed no issue between theism and pantheism. We all exist in the divine being, as St Paul said.’ 1 Classical or orthodox theists, it seems eminently fair to say, can be expected to recoil from any such suggestion with more than a little indignation. First of all, it might well be objected that Hartshorne - as a ‘process theist’ - is not a classical theist, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Cartesian Motion.Wallace E. Anderson - 1976 - In Peter K. Machamer & Robert G. Turnbull (eds.), Motion and Time, Space and Matter. Ohio State University Press.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Malebranche's doctrine of freedom / consent and the incompleteness of God's volitions.Andrew Pessin - 2000 - British Journal for the History of Philosophy 8 (1):21 – 53.
    'God needs no instruments to act', Malebranche writes in Search 6.2.3; 'it suffices that He wills in order that a thing be, because it is a contradiction that He should will and that what He wills should not happen. Therefore, His power is His will' (450). After nearly identical language in Treatise 1.12, Malebranche writes that '[God's] wills are necessarily efficacious ... [H]is power differs not at all from [H]is will' (116). God's causal power, here, clearly traces only to His (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Oakes’ New Argument for God’s Existence.Theodore J. Kondoleon - 1982 - New Scholasticism 56 (1):100-109.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Malebranche's Theodicy.Andrew G. Black - 1997 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 35 (1):27-44.
    Malebranche's Theodicy ANDREW G. BLACK LEIBNIZ'S SOLUTION tO the problem of evil, his theodicy, might be regarded as a paradigm of philosophical theology. Its pattern, as with so much of Leibniz's philosophy, is reconciliation of deep metaphysical truth with recalcitrant ap- pearance. Thus, a theodicy is not just any solution to the problem; strictly speaking it is a vindication of divine providence in the face of the challenge posed by apparent imperfections of all kinds in creation.' The preeminence of Leibniz's (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Classical Theism and Pantheism: A Victory for Process Theism?Robert A. Oakes - 1977 - Religious Studies 13 (2):167 - 173.
    In "anselm's discovery", professor hartshorne argues that there is 'no issue' between theism and pantheism. classical or orthodox theists, it seems eminently fair to say, can be expected to recoil from such a claim with more than a little indignation. what i attempt to establish, however, is that hartshorne is correct. in short, i argue that the doctrine of 'god's-constant-conservation-of-all-things' (clearly an essential or integral doctrine of classical theism) entails that the 'spatiotemporal' matrix has the property of being included within (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • A New Argument for the Existence of God.Robert A. Oakes - 1980 - New Scholasticism 54 (2):213-223.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Malebranche versus Arnauld.Monte Cook - 1991 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 29 (2):183-199.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Creation and Conservation.Hugh J. McCann - 1997 - In Charles Taliaferro & Philip L. Quinn (eds.), A Companion to Philosophy of Religion. Cambridge, Mass.: Wiley-Blackwell. pp. 315–321.
    This chapter contains sections titled: Initial Reservations Coming to Be and Being Self‐Sustenance Conservation Principles and Secondary Causes Divine Intervention Works cited.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Malebranche's natural theodicy and the incompleteness of God's volitions.Andrew Pessin - 2000 - Religious Studies 36 (1):47-63.
    The causal power of Malebranche's God is a function of the content of His will. Yet despite its significance for Malebranche, little exegetical attention has been paid to his notion of volitional content. In this paper I develop the notion of an 'incomplete' volition, note that Malebranche accepted and used something like it, and then examine Malebranche's natural theodicy in its light. This yields a new interpretation in which, unlike previous interpretations, Malebranche actually succeeds in reconciling his seemingly incompatible beliefs (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Mind-Body Interaction and Metaphysical Consistency: A Defense of Descartes.Eileen O' Neill - 1987 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 25 (2):227.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  • Leibniz and Arnauld: A Commentary on Their Correspondence. [REVIEW]Ezio Vailati - 1992 - Philosophical Review 101 (4):851-853.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   32 citations  
  • Beyond subjectivity: Spinoza's cognitivism of the emotions.Gideon Segal - 2000 - British Journal for the History of Philosophy 8 (1):1 – 19.
    In what follows I try to show that Spinoza modelled his project of rational psychology, in some of its major respects, upon Descartes's metaphysics of matter. I argue further that, like Descartes, who paid for the rationalization of the science of matter the price of having to leave out of his description non-quantifiable qualities, so Spinoza left out of his psychology the non-rationalizable aspects of emotions, i.e. whatever in them could not be subsumed under common notions. He therefore was left (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Divine Conservation and Spinozistic Pantheism: PHILIP L. QUINN.Philip L. Quinn - 1979 - Religious Studies 15 (3):289-302.
    In a recent paper, Robert A. Oakes argues that a doctrine central to, and partially constitutive of, classical theism implies a certain sort of pantheism. The doctrine in question is a modal form of the claim that God conserves in existence the world of contingent things; alternatively, it is the view that all contingently existing things are necessarily continuously dependent upon God for their existence. And the variety of pantheism at stake is a modal form of the thesis that all (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Sensation, Occasionalism, and Descartes' Causal Principles.Tad M. Schmaltz - 1992 - In Phillip D. Cummins (ed.), Minds, Ideas, and Objects: Essays on the Theory of Representation in Modern Philosophy. Ridgeview Publishing Company.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Descartes on mind-body interaction and the conservation of motion.Peter McLaughlin - 1993 - Philosophical Review 102 (2):155-182.
    The traditional (Leibnizian) reading of Descartes on mind-body interaction is given a more rigorous reformulation, explaining how Descartes could assert that the mind while not affecting the quantity of motion in the world could change its direction. It is shown, contrary to the trend in recent literature, that this reading has a reliable textual base, and it is argued that it attributes to Descartes a philosophical position of more substance and interest. The kind of interpretation favored depends on the status (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • The Cambridge Companion to Malebranche (review).Andrew Pessin - 2001 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 39 (3):442-443.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Journal of the History of Philosophy 39.3 (2001) 442-443 [Access article in PDF] Steven Nadler, editor. The Cambridge Companion to Malebranche. Cambridge Companions. New York: Cambridge University Press, 2000. Pp. xi + 319. Cloth, $54.95. With his own Cambridge Companion, the seventeenth-century French philosopher Nicolas Malebranche has at last arrived in the English speaking world. As editor Nadler puts it, "Malebranche was widely recognized by his philosophical and theological (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • How God Causes Motion.Daniel Garber - 1987 - Journal of Philosophy 84 (10):567-580.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • Continuous creation, continuous time: A refutation of the alleged discontinuity of cartesian time.Richard Arthur - 1988 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 26 (3):349-375.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations