Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. Moral saints.Susan Wolf - 1982 - Journal of Philosophy 79 (8):419-439.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   372 citations  
  • Who Are We to Judge?Thomas L. Carson - 1988 - Teaching Philosophy 11 (1):3-14.
    The proper method for dealing with meta-ethical questions in introductory ethics courses requires that the instructor consider and address at least some of the meta-ethical views most commonly held by the instructor's own students. Too often the meta-ethical views that students bring to their courses are simply ignored,.and the relation of these views to the highly abstruse theories and positions discussed in the readings and in class is not made clear. It may be the case that many popular meta-ethical views (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • An Approach to Relativism.Thomas L. Carson - 1999 - Teaching Philosophy 22 (2):161-184.
    In this paper, the author presents a lengthy class handout on moral relativism. The author treats in depth and disambiguates several senses of “moral relativism,” distinguishing between "cultural relativism," "situational relativism," "normative relativism," "metaethical relativism," "moral skepticism," and “irrationalism”. On the basis of the close attention given to these terminological differences, the author moves into a discussion of the question, “Is moral relativism true?” The author argues that while some forms of moral relativism (situational, cultural) are clearly true, others (normative) (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • The Value of Teaching Moral Skepticism.Daniel Callcut - 2006 - Teaching Philosophy 29 (3):223-235.
    This article argues that introductory ethics classes can unwittingly create or confirm skeptical views toward morality. Introductory courses frequently include critical discussion of skeptical positions such as moral relativism and psychological egoism as a way to head off this unintended outcome. But this method of forestalling skepticism can have a residual (and unintended) skeptical effect. The problem calls for deeper pedagogical-cum-philosophical engagement with the underlying sources of skepticism. The paper provides examples of how to do this and explains the additional (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Ethical theory.Richard B. Brandt - 1959 - Englewood Cliffs, N.J.: Prentice-Hall.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   108 citations  
  • Dealing with naive relativism in the philosophy classroom.Judith Andre - 1983 - Metaphilosophy 14 (2):179–182.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Student Relativism.Stephen A. Satris - 1986 - Teaching Philosophy 9 (3):193-205.
    In this paper I offer an analysis of, and suggest some methods for dealing with, a quite particular and peculiar problem in teaching philosophy. It is, perhaps,not a problem essential to the discipline or to its teaching, but it is nevertheless one of the most serious, pervasive, and frustrating problems confronting mostphilosophy teachers today. I speak of the problem of student relativism-or, SR for short.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Popular Subjectivism and Relativism.Charles L. Reid - 1970 - Journal of Critical Analysis 2 (3):36-42.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • The Student Relativist as Philosopher.Roger Paden - 1987 - Teaching Philosophy 10 (2):97-101.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Teaching Ethics to Student Relativists.Richard W. Momeyer - 1995 - Teaching Philosophy 18 (4):301-311.
    Following from the critiques of moral relativism advanced by philosophers such as Gilbert Harman and J.L. Mackie, the author explores philosophical challenges that educators face in philosophy courses. Specifically, the author accounts for the new wave of moral relativism and its effects on classroom discussions in philosophy courses. The purpose of this paper is to outline various pedagogical approaches that help with identifying student relativism. Unlike philosophical relativism, student relativism can be identified as an unreflective response to or attitude towards (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Engaging Student Aversions to Moral Obligations.Court D. Lewis - 2015 - Teaching Philosophy 38 (3):273-288.
    This essay examines why some introductory ethics students are averse to any sort of moral requirement. It provides a series of descriptions and techniques to help teachers recognize, diagnose, and engage such students. After discussing the nature of student aversions to moral obligations, I discuss three causes and several ways to engage each: 1) Student Relativism; 2) student fears and misunderstandings of obligations; and 3) the phenomenon of what I call fetishized liberty, which leads to the “liberty paradox”—where students actively (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Moral Skepticism and Tolerance.Craig K. Ihara - 1984 - Teaching Philosophy 7 (3):193-198.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • On Moral Relativism, Advocacy, and Teaching Normative Ethics.Michael Goldman - 1981 - Teaching Philosophy 4 (1):1-11.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • In a Different Voice: Psychological Theory and Women’s Development.Carol Gilligan - 1982 - The Personalist Forum 2 (2):150-152.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2014 citations  
  • The truth, but not yet: Avoiding naïve skepticism via explicit communication of metadisciplinary aims.Jake Wright - 2019 - Teaching in Higher Education 24 (3):361-377.
    Introductory students regularly endorse naïve skepticism—unsupported or uncritical doubt about the existence and universality of truth—for a variety of reasons. Though some of the reasons for students’ skepticism can be traced back to the student—for example, a desire to avoid engaging with controversial material or a desire to avoid offense—naïve skepticism is also the result of how introductory courses are taught, deemphasizing truth to promote students’ abilities to develop basic disciplinary skills. While this strategy has a number of pedagogical benefits, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Tolerance and Evil: Teaching the Holocaust.Berel Lang - 1984 - Teaching Philosophy 7 (3):199-203.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Logical Foundations of Probability.Rudolf Carnap - 1950 - Mind 62 (245):86-99.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   868 citations  
  • The Natural History of Student Relativism.Roger Paden - 1994 - Journal of Thought 29 (2):47-59.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Unsolvable Problems and Philosophical Progress.William J. Rapaport - 1982 - American Philosophical Quarterly 19 (4):289 - 298.
    Philosophy has been characterized (e.g., by Benson Mates) as a field whose problems are unsolvable. This has often been taken to mean that there can be no progress in philosophy as there is in mathematics or science. The nature of problems and solutions is considered, and it is argued that solutions are always parts of theories, hence that acceptance of a solution requires commitment to a theory (as suggested by William Perry's scheme of cognitive development). Progress can be had in (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   22 citations  
  • The Concept of Morals.W. T. Stace - 1937 - Philosophy 13 (50):235-236.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations