Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. Language as a Natural Object.Noam Chomsky - 2000 - In New horizons in the study of language and mind. New York: Cambridge University Press. pp. 106--133.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   238 citations  
  • Thoughts and Utterances: The Pragmatics of Explicit Communication. [REVIEW]Anne Bezuidenhout - 2005 - Mind 114 (455):722-728.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   238 citations  
  • Wittgenstein on family resemblance concepts.Michael Forster - 2010 - In Arif Ahmed (ed.), Wittgenstein's Philosophical investigations: a critical guide. New York: Cambridge University Press.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  • A Note on the Concept of Game.Paul Hoyningen-Huene - 2015 - In Gregor Betz, Dirk Koppelberg, David Lüwenstein & Anna Wehofsits (eds.), Weiter Denken - Über Philosophie, Wissenschaft Und Religion. Boston: De Gruyter. pp. 205-210.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Understanding the 'What-is-F?' Question.David Wolfsdorf - 2003 - Apeiron 36 (3):175 - 188.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Reasons and causes in the phaedo.Gregory Vlastos - 1969 - Philosophical Review 78 (3):291-325.
    An analysis of phaedo 96c-606c seeks to demonstrate that when forms are cited as either "safe" or "clever" aitiai they are not meant to function as either final or efficient causes, But as logico-Metaphysical essences which have no causal efficacy whatever, But which do have definite (and far-Reaching) implications for the causal order of the physical universe, For it is assumed that a causal statement, Such as "fire causes heat" will be true if, And only if, The asserted physical bond (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   57 citations  
  • Plato on Metaphysical Explanation: Does 'Participating' Mean Nothing?Christine J. Thomas - 2014 - Studia Philosophica Estonica 7 (2):168.
    According to Aristotle, Plato's efforts at metaphysical explanation not only fail, they are nonsensical. In particular, Plato's appeals to Forms as metaphysically explanatory of the sensibles that participate in them is "empty talk" since "'participating' means nothing". I defend Plato against Aristotle's charge by identifying a particular, substantive model of metaphysical predication as the favored model of Plato's late ontology. The model posits two basic metaphysical predication relations: self-predication and participation. In order to understand the participation relation, it is important (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Plato’s Individuals.Allan Silverman & Mary Margaret McCabe - 1997 - Philosophical Review 106 (3):470.
    Plato's Individuals is rich and rewarding. McCabe's reading will compel us to examine anew the presuppositions we bring to the enterprise of understanding Plato. Her devotion to showing that her thesis is found almost everywhere in the corpus is noteworthy. At times she also seems to strain to assimilate modern and Platonic concerns. If one can accept that Plato's tripartite soul goes over into something we might recognize as the problem of personal identity, it can only be because we are (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Platonic Causes.David Sedley - 1998 - Phronesis 43 (2):114-132.
    This paper examines Plato's ideas on cause-effect relations in the "Phaedo." It maintains that he sees causes as things (not events, states of affairs or the like), with any information as to how that thing brings about the effect relegated to a strictly secondary status. This is argued to make good sense, so long as we recognise that aition means the "thing responsible" and exploit legal analogies in order to understand what this amounts to. Furthermore, provided that we do not (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   64 citations  
  • Something common.Robert J. Richman - 1962 - Journal of Philosophy 59 (26):821-830.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Literal Meaning. [REVIEW]Kent Bach - 2007 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 75 (2):487-492.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   293 citations  
  • The Concept of Παπάδειγμα in Plato's Theory of Forms.William J. Prior - 1983 - Apeiron 17 (1):33-42.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Thought and Language.Julius M. MORAVCSIK - 1994 - Philosophical Review 103 (1):144.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Thought and Language.Uwe Monnich & J. M. Moravcsik - 1994 - Philosophical Review 103 (1):144.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Plato's Phaedo.Constance C. Meinwald & David Bostock - 1989 - Philosophical Review 98 (1):127.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   41 citations  
  • Complex Property Structure in Plato’s Philebus.Harry A. Ide - 2002 - Ancient Philosophy 22 (2):263-276.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Wittgenstein, Universals and Family Resemblances.Nicholas Griffin - 1974 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 3 (4):635 - 651.
    Wittgenstein expounds his notion of a family resemblance in two important passages. The first is from The Blue Book:This craving for generality is the resultant of a number of tendencies connected with particular philosophical confusions. There is— The tendency to look for something common to entities which we commonly subsume under a general term. We are inclined to think that there must be something common to all games, say, and that this common property is the justification for applying the general (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Family resemblances and criteria.Heather J. Gert - 1995 - Synthese 105 (2):177-190.
    In §66 ofPhilosophical Investigations Wittgenstein looks for something common to various games and finds only an interconnecting network of resemblances. These are family resemblances. Sympathetic as well as unsympathetic readers have interpreted him as claiming that games form a family in virtue of these resemblances. This assumes Wittgenstein inverted the relation between being a member of a family and bearing family resemblances to others of that family. (The Churchills bear family resemblances to one another because they belong to the same (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Plato on what the body's eye tells the mind's eye.Dorothea Frede - 1999 - Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 99 (2):191–209.
    Though the two-world interpretation of Plato's metaphysics is no longer uncontested the question of the expendability of the physical world still predominates current discussions. Against this tendency the article suggests that Plato neither intended to dispose of sensory evidence altogether nor to locate the Forms in a separate realm of pure understanding. The Forms should rather be understood as the ideal principles determining the proper function of each entity. Such a 'functional view' of the Forms is discussed explicitly in Book (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Plato's metaphysical epistemology.Nicholas P. White - 1992 - In Richard Kraut (ed.), The Cambridge Companion to Plato. Cambridge University Press. pp. 277--310.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • Introducing substance concepts.Ruth G. Millikan - 2000 - In On Clear and Confused Ideas. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   65 citations  
  • Equal sticks and stones.David Sedley - 2007 - In Dominic Scott (ed.), Maieusis: Essays in Ancient Philosophy in Honour of Myles Burnyeat. Oxford University Press.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Plato’s Individuals.Mary Margaret McCabe - 1994 - Philosophy 70 (274):594-598.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   24 citations  
  • Philosophical investigations.Ludwig Wittgenstein & G. E. M. Anscombe - 1953 - Revue Philosophique de la France Et de l'Etranger 161:124-124.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2235 citations  
  • The Blue and Brown Books.Ludwig Wittgenstein - 1958 - Philosophy 34 (131):367-368.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   443 citations  
  • The Dialectic of Essence: A Study of Plato's Metaphysics.Allan Silverman - 2005 - Philosophical Quarterly 55 (220):507-510.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  • Plato on the Imperfection of the Sensible World.Alexander Nehamas - 1975 - American Philosophical Quarterly 12 (2):105 - 117.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   27 citations  
  • Self-Predication and Plato's Theory of Forms.Alexander Nehamas - 1979 - American Philosophical Quarterly 16 (2):93 - 103.
    This paper offers an interpretation of self-Predication (the idea that justice is just) in plato, Given that self-Predication is accepted as obvious both by plato and by his audience, Which entails that "all" self-Predications are clearly, Though not trivially, True. More strongly, It is suggested that "only" self-Predications can be accepted as clearly true by plato. This is to deny that plato had at his disposal an articulated notion of predication, And his middle theory of forms, Primarily the relation of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations