Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. Purism: The Inconceivability of Inconsistency within Space as the Basis of Logic.* Primus - 2019 - Dialogue 62 (1):1-24.
    I propose that an irreducible property of physical space — consistency — is the origin of logic. I propose that an inconsistent space is inconceivable and that this inconceivability can be recognized as the force behind logical propositions. The implications of this argument are briefly explored and then applied to address two paradoxes: Zeno of Elea’s paradox regarding the race between Achilles and the Tortoise, and Lewis Carroll’s paradox regarding the Tortoise’s conversation with Achilles after the race. I conclude that (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Hume on the Passions.Stephen Buckle - 2012 - Philosophy 87 (2):189-213.
    Hume's account of the passions is largely neglected because the author's purposes tend to be missed. The passions were accepted by early modern philosophers, of whatever persuasion, as the mental effects of bodily processes. The dualist and the materialist differed over whether reason is a higher power able to judge and control them: thus Descartes affirms, whereas Hobbes denies, this possibility.Hume's account lines up firmly behind Hobbes. Although he shies away from Hobbes's dogmatic physiological claims, he affirms all the key (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Korsgaard v. Gewirth on Universalization: Why Gewirthians are Kantians and Kantians Ought to be Gewirthians.D. Beyleveld - 2014 - Journal of Moral Philosophy 11 (4).
    Christine Korsgaard claims that Gewirth’s argument for morality fails to demonstrate that there is a categorically binding principle on action because it operates with the assumption that reasons for action are essentially private. This attribution is unfounded and Korsgaard’s own argument for moral obligation, in its appeal to Wittgenstein’s Private Language Argument to establish that reasons for action are essentially public, is misdirected and unnecessary. Gewirth’s attempt to demonstrate a strictly a priori connection between a moral principle and the concept (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Korsgaard v. Gewirth on Universalization: Why Gewirthians are Kantians and Kantians Ought to be Gewirthians.Deryck Beyleveld - 2014 - Journal of Moral Philosophy 11 (4):573-597.
    Christine Korsgaard claims that Gewirth’s argument for morality fails to demonstrate that there is a categorically binding principle on action because it operates with the assumption that reasons for action are essentially private. This attribution is unfounded and Korsgaard’s own argument for moral obligation, in its appeal to Wittgenstein’s Private Language Argument to establish that reasons for action are essentially public, is misdirected and unnecessary. Gewirth’s attempt to demonstrate a strictly a priori connection between a moral principle and the concept (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Korsgaard v. Gewirth on Universalization: Why Gewirthians are Kantians and Kantians Ought to be Gewirthians.Deryck Beyleveld - 2015 - Journal of Moral Philosophy 12 (5):573-597.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • How to derive "ought" from "is".John R. Searle - 1964 - Philosophical Review 73 (1):43-58.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   180 citations  
  • Varieties of Objectivity and Values.A. W. Price - 1983 - Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 83:103 - 119.
    A. W. Price; VII*—Varieties of Objectivity and Values, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Volume 83, Issue 1, 1 June 1983, Pages 103–120, https://doi.org/.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • VII*—Varieties of Objectivity and Values.A. W. Price - 1983 - Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 83 (1):103-120.
    A. W. Price; VII*—Varieties of Objectivity and Values, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Volume 83, Issue 1, 1 June 1983, Pages 103–120, https://doi.org/.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Fellow Creatures. Our Obligations to the Other Animals.Christine M. Korsgaard - 2018 - Zeitschrift für Philosophische Forschung 73 (1):165-168.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   102 citations  
  • Anarchy, State, and Utopia.Robert Nozick - 1974 - Philosophy 52 (199):102-105.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1999 citations  
  • Fellow creatures: Kantian ethics and our duties to animals.Christine M. Korsgaard - unknown
    Christine M. Korsgaard is Arthur Kingsley Porter Professor of Philosophy at Harvard University. She was educated at the University of Illinois and received a Ph.D. from Harvard. She has held positions at Yale, the University of California at Santa Barbara, and the University of Chicago, and visiting positions at Berkeley and UCLA. She is a member of the American Philosophical Association and a fellow of the American Academy of Arts and Sciences. She has published extensively on Kant, and about moral (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   71 citations  
  • Whom Would Animals Designate as Persons? On the Avoidance of Anthropocentrism and the Inclusion of Others.Elizabeth Oriel - 2014 - Journal of Evolution and Technology 24 (3):44-59.
    Humans are animals; humans are machines. The current academic and popular dialogue on extending the personhood boundary to certain non-human animal species and at the same time to machines/robots reflects a dialectic about how “being human” is defined; about how we perceive our species and ourselves in relation to the environment. While both paths have the potential to improve lives; these improvements differ in substance and in consequence. One route has the potential to broaden the anthropocentric focus within the West (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Purism: Logic as the Basis of Morality.* Primus - 2021 - Essays in the Philosophy of Humanism 29:1-36.
    In this article I attempt to overcome extant obstacles in deriving fundamental, objective and logically deduced definitions of personhood and their rights, by introducing an a priori paradigm of beings and morality. I do so by drawing a distinction between entities that are sought as ends and entities that are sought as means to said ends. The former entities, I offer, are the essence of personhood and are considered precious by observers possessing a logical system of valuation. The latter entities (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Passion and Value in Hume's Treatise.Páll S. ÁRdal - 1966 - Revue Philosophique de la France Et de l'Etranger 164 (4):466-467.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   22 citations  
  • Evolving Notions of Nonhuman Personhood: Is Moral Standing Sufficient?Dorothy Riddle - 2014 - Journal of Evolution and Technology 24 (3):4-19.
    Decisions regarding the attribution of personhood to nonhuman animals have implications not only for the rights held by a particular species but also for the moral obligations of humans as moral agents. Since humans decide which species are accorded moral standing; thus becoming candidates for legal standing as legal persons; we need to be aware of our own vested interests in where the boundaries of duty are drawn. This paper argues that simple determination of moral standing is not sufficient to (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Reason and Morality.Alan Gewirth - 1968 - Philosophy 56 (216):266-267.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   126 citations  
  • The Community of Rights.Alan Gewirth - 1997 - Philosophy 72 (282):609-612.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   38 citations