Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. The emotional experience of the sublime.Tom Cochrane - 2012 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 42 (2):125-148.
    The literature on the venerable aesthetic category of the sublime often provides us with lists of sublime phenomena — mountains, storms, deserts, volcanoes, oceans, the starry sky, and so on. But it has long been recognized that what matters is the experience of such objects. We then find that one of the most consistent claims about this experience is that it involves an element of fear. Meanwhile, the recognition of the sublime as a category of aesthetic appreciation implies that attraction, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • Reassessing Aesthetic Appreciation of Nature in the Kantian Sublime.Emily Brady - 2012 - Journal of Aesthetic Education 46 (1):91-109.
    The sublime has been a relatively neglected topic in recent work in philosophical aesthetics, with existing discussions confined mainly to problems in Kant's theory.1 Given the revival of interest in his aesthetic theory and the influence of the Kantian sublime compared to other eighteenth-century accounts, this focus is not surprising. Kant's emphasis on nature also sets his theory apart from other eighteenth-century theories that, although making nature central, also give explicit attention to moral character and mathematical ideas and generally devote (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Longinus, the ‘Philological Discourses’, and the Essay ‘On the Sublime’.M. J. Boyd - 1957 - Classical Quarterly 7 (1-2):39-46.
    It has long been known that two medieval scholiasts, one of them called John of Sicily, the other anonymous, commenting on a passage of Hermogenes', ascribe what looks like a passage of the de Sublimitate to ‘Longinus’. On the assumption, however, that the ‘Longinus’ referred to must be Cassius Longinus, the third-century rhetorician, scholars have tended to minimize the vweight of the evidence and attempted to explain it away. For it is now established that the de Sublimitate must date from (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Dionysius and Longinus on the Sublime: Rhetoric and Religious Language.Casper de - 2012 - American Journal of Philology 133 (2):271-300.
    Longinus' On the Sublime presents itself as a response to the work of the Augustan critic Caecilius of Caleacte. Recent attempts to reconstruct Longinus' intellectual context have largely ignored the works of Dionysius of Halicarnassus, Caecilius' contemporary colleague. This article investigates the concept of hupsos and its religious aspects in Longinus and Dionysius, and reveals a remarkable continuity between the discourse of both authors. Dionysius' works inform us about an Augustan debate on Plato and the sublime, and thereby provide us (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • De la philosophie à la rhétorique.Juliette Dross - 2004 - Philosophie Antique 4 (4):61-93.
    This paper aims to reconstruct the history of the link drawn up by Pseudo-Longinus and Quintilian between phantasia, defined as a faculty of mental visualization, and enargeia, that is the self-evidence of the speech. Actually, the two notions are already linked in the Stoa, which associates enargeia with the « comprehensive representation » (phantasia kataleptike), defined as the support of knowledge and action. The treatise On the Sublime suggests a shift from the Stoic definition of phantasia, considered as « common (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Dionysius and Longinus on the Sublime: Rhetoric and Religious Language.Casper C. de Jonge - 2012 - American Journal of Philology 133 (2):271-300.
    Longinus' On the Sublime presents itself as a response to the work of the Augustan critic Caecilius of Caleacte. Recent attempts to reconstruct Longinus' intellectual context have largely ignored the works of Dionysius of Halicarnassus, Caecilius' contemporary colleague . This article investigates the concept of hupsos and its religious aspects in Longinus and Dionysius, and reveals a remarkable continuity between the discourse of both authors. Dionysius' works inform us about an Augustan debate on Plato and the sublime, and thereby provide (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Appearances and assent: Sceptical belief reconsidered.Katja Maria Vogt - 2012 - Classical Quarterly 62 (2):648-663.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  • Images, Appearances, and Phantasia in Aristotle.Krisanna M. Scheiter - 2012 - Phronesis 57 (3):251-278.
    Abstract Aristotle's account of Phantasia in De Anima 3.3 is notoriously difficult to decipher. At one point he describes Phantasia as a capacity for producing images, but then later in the same chapter it is clear Phantasia is supposed to explain appearances, such as why the sun appears to be a foot wide. Many commentators argue that images cannot explain appearances, and so they claim that Aristotle is using Phantasia in two different ways. In this paper I argue that images (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  • Mimesis or Phantasia? Two Representational\\ Modes in Roman Commemorative Art.Michael Koortbojian - 2005 - Classical Antiquity 24 (2):285-306.
    The commemorative forms of the Romans are marked by the ubiquity of two contrasting presentational modes: one essentially mimetic, rooted in the representational power of artistic forms, the other abstract and figurative, dependent on the presentation of cues for the summoning of absent yet necessary images. The mimetic mode was thoroughly conventional, and thus posed few problems of interpretation; the figurative knew no such orthodoxy and required a different and distinctive form of attention. At the tomb, epigraphic and sculptural forms, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • (1 other version)Chrysippe.G. S. Brett - 1911 - Philosophical Review 20 (5):551.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Sappho in "Longinus".W. B. Sedgwick - 1948 - American Journal of Philology 69 (2):197.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Mimesis und Phantasia.Bernhard Schweitzer - 1934 - Philologus: Zeitschrift für Antike Literatur Und Ihre Rezeption 89 (1-4):290-304.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Le « critère de vérité » (κριτήριον τῆς ἀληθείας) comme outil hellénistique de classification des systèmes philosophiques.Marwan Rashed - 2015 - Les Etudes Philosophiques 112 (1):65-82.
    Cet article s’interroge sur le sens et la portée de la similitude, semble-t-il jamais explicitement formulée par Jules Vuillemin, entre sa classification des systèmes philosophiques et l’opposition des quatre grands systèmes antiques (platonisme, aristotélisme, épicurisme, stoïcisme) sur la question du critère de vérité (????????????????????). Il suggère ensuite d’assimiler l’opposition entre analyse et synthèse des systèmes philosophiques telle que la reconstitue Jules Vuillemin à celle que le philosophe assigne à la métaphysique, par opposition à la mathématique, cartésienne.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Représentation et évidence: les Stoïciens face à leurs adversaires de l’Académie.René Lefebvre - 2007 - Elenchos 28 (2):337-368.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Faut-il traduire le vocable aristotélicien de 'phantasia' par 'représentation'?René Lefebvre - 1997 - Revue Philosophique De Louvain 95 (4):587-616.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • “A City of Brick”: Visual Rhetoric in Roman Rhetorical Theory and Practice.Kathleen S. Lamp - 2011 - Philosophy and Rhetoric 44 (2):171-193.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:"A City of Brick":Visual Rhetoric in Roman Rhetorical Theory and PracticeKathleen S. LampPerhaps none of the words Augustus, the first sole ruler of Rome who reigned from 27 BCE to 14 CE, actually said are quite as memorable as the ones Cassius Dio has attributed to him: "I found Rome built of clay and I leave it to you in marble" (1987, 56.30).1 Suetonius too discusses Augustus's building program, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Science Sublime: The Philosophy of the Sublime, Dewey's Aesthetics, and Science Education.Shane Cavanaugh - 2014 - Education and Culture 30 (1):57-77.
    Due to the historic separation of cognition and emotion, the affective aspects of learning are often seen as trivial in comparison to the more ‘essential’ cognitive qualities—particularly in science. We are taught that science should objectively scrutinize the world in search of answers, and science educators have been taught to look to scientists to guide their teaching of content and processes.2 As a result, science pedagogy characteristically instructs students to step back from objects and events in order to dispassionately observe (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations