Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. Are Dispositions Causes?Leslie Stevenson - 1969 - Analysis 29 (6):197 - 199.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Are Dispositions Lost Causes?Roger Squires - 1970 - Analysis 31 (1):15 - 18.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • The problem of counterfactuals.R. S. Walters - 1961 - Australasian Journal of Philosophy 39 (1):30-46.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Studies in the empiricist theory of scientific meaning.William W. Rozeboom - 1960 - Philosophy of Science 27 (4):359-373.
    Part I is concerned with the tenet of modern Emperical Realism that while the theoretical concepts employed in science obtain their meanings entirely from the connections their usage establishes with the data language, the referents of such terms may be "unobservables," that is, entities which cannot be discussed within the data language alone. Such a view avoids both the restrictive excesses of logical positivism and the epistemic laxity of transcendentalism; however, it also necessitates a break with classical semantics, for it (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • New dimensions of confirmation theory.William W. Rozeboom - 1968 - Philosophy of Science 35 (2):134-155.
    When Hempel's "paradox of confirmation" is developed within the confines of conditional probability theory, it becomes apparent that two seemingly equivalent generalities ("laws") can have exactly the same class of observational refuters even when their respective classes of confirming observations are importantly distinct. Generalities which have the inductive supports we commonsensically construe them to have, however, must incorporate quasi-logical operators or connectives which cannot be defined truth-functionally. The origins and applications of these "modalic" concepts appear to be intimately linked with (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Ontological induction and the logical typology of scientific variables.William W. Rozeboom - 1961 - Philosophy of Science 28 (4):337-377.
    It is widely agreed among philosophers of science today that no formal pattern can possibly be found in the origins of scientific theory. There is no such thing as a "logic of discovery," insists this view--a scientific hypothesis is susceptible to methodological critique only in its relation to empirical consequences derived after the hypothesis itself has emerged through a spontaneous creative inspiration. Yet confronted with the tautly directed thrust of theory-building as actually practiced at the cutting edge of scientific research, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   27 citations  
  • Of selection operators and semanticists.William W. Rozeboom - 1964 - Philosophy of Science 31 (3):282-285.
    As anyone who has ever seriously attempted to analyze the semantico-epistemological status of scientific theories has soon discovered, it is not easy to reconcile the belief that theoretical terms have genuine cognitive properties with the empiricist tenet that all knowledge derives from experience. Even if it be granted that knowledge can originate in experience without being about experience, it still remains to develop a coherent metalinguistic account of the truth-conditions of theoretical propositions and the designata of denotative expressions in the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Intentionality and existence.William W. Rozeboom - 1962 - Mind 71 (January):15-32.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Belief-contravening suppositions.Nicholas Rescher - 1961 - Philosophical Review 70 (2):176-196.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • The Powerlessness of Dispositions.Brian O'Shaughnessy - 1970 - Analysis 31 (1):1 - 15.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Powers.R. Harré - 1970 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 21 (1):81-101.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   52 citations  
  • Some Misconceptions about Dispositions.David Coder - 1969 - Analysis 29 (6):200 - 202.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • The contrary-to-fact conditional.Roderick M. Chisholm - 1946 - Mind 55 (220):289-307.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   87 citations  
  • Dispositions are causes.David Malet Armstrong - 1969 - Analysis 30 (1):23-26.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   28 citations  
  • Dispositions and Occurrences.William P. Alston - 1971 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 1 (2):125 - 154.
    Since the publication of Gilbert Ryle's book, The Concept of Mind, the distinction between dispositions and occurrences has loomed large in the philosophy of mind. In that enormously influential book Ryle set out to show that much of what passes as mental is best construed as dispositional in character rather than, as traditionally supposed, being made up of private “ghostly” occurrences, ‘happenings, or “episodes.” Many philosophers, including some of Ryle's ablest critics, have accepted the terms of Ryle's contentions. They have (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Philosophy of Science.Gustav Bergmann - 1958 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 9 (35):247-248.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  • The Psychology of Knowing.J. R. Royce & W. W. Rozeboom - 1973 - Philosophy of Science 40 (2):322-323.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations