Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. Proof Theory.Gaisi Takeuti - 1990 - Studia Logica 49 (1):160-161.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   165 citations  
  • Logical constants as punctuation marks.Kosta Došen - 1989 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 30 (3):362-381.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   63 citations  
  • Display logic.Nuel D. Belnap - 1982 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 11 (4):375-417.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   112 citations  
  • Embedding classical logic into basic orthologic with a primitive modality.G. Battilotti - 1998 - Logic Journal of the IGPL 6 (3):383-402.
    In the present paper we give the first proof-theoretical example of an embedding of classical logic into a quantum-like logic. This is performed in the framework of basic logic, where a proof-theoretical approach to quantum logic is convenient. We consider basic orthologic, that corresponds to a sequential formulation of paraconsistent quantum logic, and which is given by basic orthologic added with weakening and contraction, in a language with Girard's negation. In the paper we first consider a convenient cut-free calculus for (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Elements of Intuitionism.Michael Dummett - 1980 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 31 (3):299-301.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   206 citations  
  • (1 other version)Proof Theory and Logical Complexity.Helmut Pfeifer & Jean-Yves Girard - 1989 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 54 (4):1493.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   48 citations  
  • On the unity of logic.Jean-Yves Girard - 1993 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 59 (3):201-217.
    We present a single sequent calculus common to classical, intuitionistic and linear logics. The main novelty is that classical, intuitionistic and linear logics appear as fragments, i.e. as particular classes of formulas and sequents. For instance, a proof of an intuitionistic formula A may use classical or linear lemmas without any restriction: but after cut-elimination the proof of A is wholly intuitionistic, what is superficially achieved by the subformula property and more deeply by a very careful treatment of structural rules. (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   25 citations