Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. Actions, Reasons, and Causes.Donald Davidson - 1963 - Journal of Philosophy 60 (23):685.
    What is the relation between a reason and an action when the reason explains the action by giving the agent's reason for doing what he did? We may call such explanations rationalizations, and say that the reason rationalizes the action. In this paper I want to defend the ancient - and common-sense - position that rationalization is a species of ordinary causal explanation. The defense no doubt requires some redeployment, but not more or less complete abandonment of the position, as (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1242 citations  
  • Socrates on the definition of Piety.S. Marc Cohen - 1971 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 9 (1):1-13.
    The central argument in the Euthyphro is the one Socrates advances against the definition of piety as "what all the gods love." The argument turns on establishing that a loved thing (philoumenon) is 1) a loved thing because it is loved (phileitai), not 2) loved because it is a loved thing. I suggest that this claim can be understood and found acceptable if we take "because" to be used equivocally in it. Despite the equivocation, Socrates' argument is valid, showing that (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  • Doing Business with the Gods.Steven A. M. Burns - 1985 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 15 (2):311 - 325.
    Plato's Euthyphro is a dialogue about the virtue of piety. It is also one of the aporetic dialogues, ending in apparent failure to discover what piety is. It is common to understand the dialogue as teaching lessons about other things, about definition, for instance, or about the logic of refutation. About piety, however, it is thought to teach us only negatively, showing a few of the many things which piety is not.My thesis, on the contrary, is that there is a (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • The logic of the euthyphro 10a-11b.John H. Brown - 1964 - Philosophical Quarterly 14 (54):1-14.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • A "Conception" of Truth in Plato's Sophist.Blake E. Hestir - 2003 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 41 (1):1-24.
    I argue that in Plato's _Sophist, the account of true and false statement which emerges within the discussion of not being and falsehood neither entails nor outwardly suggests any of the traditional characterizations of a correspondence "theory" of truth. On the contrary, what emerges is a minimalistic "conception" of truth which requires neither positing the existence of facts nor formulating an explanatory definition of truth. I make comparisons with Aristotle's discussion of truth in the _Categories and _De Interpretatione, and I (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Explanatory unification and the problem of asymmetry.Eric Barnes - 1992 - Philosophy of Science 59 (4):558-571.
    Philip Kitcher has proposed a theory of explanation based on the notion of unification. Despite the genuine interest and power of the theory, I argue here that the theory suffers from a fatal deficiency: It is intrinsically unable to account for the asymmetric structure of explanation, and thus ultimately falls prey to a problem similar to the one which beset Hempel's D-N model. I conclude that Kitcher is wrong to claim that one can settle the issue of an argument's explanatory (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   41 citations  
  • Explanatory unification.Philip Kitcher - 1981 - Philosophy of Science 48 (4):507-531.
    The official model of explanation proposed by the logical empiricists, the covering law model, is subject to familiar objections. The goal of the present paper is to explore an unofficial view of explanation which logical empiricists have sometimes suggested, the view of explanation as unification. I try to show that this view can be developed so as to provide insight into major episodes in the history of science, and that it can overcome some of the most serious difficulties besetting the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   576 citations  
  • Euthyphro's failure.Roslyn Weiss - 1986 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 24 (4):437-452.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Plato's Causal Logic and the Third Man Argument.Richard Sharvy - 1986 - Noûs 20 (4):507-530.
    (1) anything that fs does so because it participates in the f itself. (2) it is impossible that: a form phi fs because phi participates in phi. (3) the f itself fs. These are inconsistent all right, but (1) is not a doctrine of the theory of forms, and (2) is neither reasonable nor held by plato! but the tma does not involve any of these three. Rather, the tma is aimed at (4) anything that fs does so (a) because (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Euthyphro 9d-11b: Analysis and Definition in Plato and Others.Richard Sharvy - 1972 - Noûs 6 (2):119-137.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  • A logic for 'because'.Benjamin Schnieder - 2011 - Review of Symbolic Logic 4 (3):445-465.
    In spite of its significance for everyday and philosophical discourse, the explanatory connective has not received much treatment in the philosophy of logic. The present paper develops a logic for based on systematic connections between and the truth-functional connectives.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   119 citations  
  • The socratic fallacy.Gerasimos Xenophon Santas - 1972 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 10 (2):127-141.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Frege's theory of predication: An elaboration and defense, with some new applications.Ian Rumfitt - 1994 - Philosophical Review 103 (4):599-637.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  • A Note on the Euthyphro, 10-11.Lynn E. Rose - 1965 - Phronesis 10 (2):149-150.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Plato's Euthyphro 10 a to 11 b.Thomas D. Paxson - 1972 - Phronesis 17 (2):171 - 190.
    That 'what all the gods love is holy (pious) and, on the other hand, what they all hate is unholy (impious)' is not an adequate account of the holy. The key to understanding the argument is found to rest in the epagogai and in the principle of substitutibility employed later in socrates' argument. I contend that not only is socrates' argument valid, but it is capable of application to a large class of accounts both theological and sociological.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • The Euthyphro Argument (9d–11b).Brendan O'Sullivan - 2010 - Southern Journal of Philosophy 44 (4):657-675.
    A sizable literature exists concerning the structure of Socrates' argument at Euthyphro 9d–11b. Although there is some dispute, a substitutional reading has emerged as a leading interpretation. However, some rear‐guard maneuvers are in order to defend this reading against its competitors. In this paper, I articulate a substitutional reading and argue that it is invalid on two counts: one, Socrates oversteps the logic of his reductio ad absurdum, and two, he illicitly substitutes coreferring expressions in explanatory contexts. Next, I defend (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • The Euthyphro Argument (9d–11b).Brendan O'Sullivan - 2010 - Southern Journal of Philosophy 44 (4):657-675.
    A sizable literature exists concerning the structure of Socrates' argument at Euthyphro 9d–11b. Although there is some dispute, a substitutional reading has emerged as a leading interpretation. However, some rear‐guard maneuvers are in order to defend this reading against its competitors. In this paper, I articulate a substitutional reading and argue that it is invalid on two counts: one, Socrates oversteps the logic of his reductio ad absurdum, and two, he illicitly substitutes coreferring expressions in explanatory contexts. Next, I defend (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Plato's Euthyphro, Apology of Socrates, and Crito.Glenn R. Morrow & John Burnet - 1925 - Philosophical Review 34 (4):412.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • Socratic Piety In The Euthyphro.Mark L. McPherran - 1985 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 23 (3):283-309.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  • Piety: Lending a hand to euthyphro.William E. Mann - 1998 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 58 (1):123-142.
    Many philosophers take the point of Plato's Euthyphro to be an indictment of attempts to ground morality in religion, specifically in the attitudes of a deity or deities. It has been argued cogently in recent essays that Plato's case is far from conclusive. This essay suggests instead that the Euthyphro can be read more narrowly as raising critical questions about a specific religious virtue, Piety. Then it presents the ingredients of a reply to those questions. The reply proceeds by suggesting (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Theistic ethics and the "euthyphro".James H. Lesher - 1975 - Apeiron 9 (2):24 - 30.
    A. E. Taylor states the widely held view that Plato’s Euthyphro posed a question which figured prominently in later ethical controversies: “It amounts to asking whether acts of piety, or more generally virtuous acts, derive their character of being right from the mere fact of being commanded or are commanded because they are antecedently intrinsically right.” I argue against this characterization of the Euthyphro. The argument Socrates deploys against Euthyphro’s third and most serious definition of holiness or piety (to hosion) (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • A Chiastic Contradiction at Euthyphro 9e1-11b5. Kim - 2004 - Phronesis 49 (3):219-224.
    One of Euthyphro's proposed definitions of to hosion says: '[T]he pious is what all the gods love...'. Scholarly analyses of Socrates' refutation of this definition have focused on its validity or even its 'truth'. By contrast, this paper restricts itself to the refutation's logical structure, particularly the way Socrates juxtaposes the agreed-upon premises to derive a double or 'chiastic' contradiction. In this article, I lay out the details of Socrates' ingenious logical construction, without regard to its validity or fallaciousness, and (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Theistic Ethics and the Euthyphro Dilemma.Richard Joyce - 2002 - Journal of Religious Ethics 30 (1):49-75.
    It is widely believed that the Divine Command Theory is untenable due to the Euthyphro Dilemma. This article first examines the Platonic dialogue of that name, and shows that Socrates’s reasoning is faulty. Second, the dilemma in the form in which many contemporary philosophers accept it is examined in detail, and this reasoning is also shown to be deficient. This is not to say, however, that the Divine Command Theory is true—merely that one popular argument for rejecting it is unsound. (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   21 citations  
  • Plato's Euthyphro.Robert G. Hoerber - 1958 - Phronesis 3 (2):95 - 107.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Plato: Euthyphro 10a1-11a10.John C. Hall - 1968 - Philosophical Quarterly 18 (70):1-11.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Plato’s Euthyphro: An Analysis and Commentary.P. T. Geach - 1966 - The Monist 50 (3):369-382.
    The Euthyphro might well be given to undergraduates to read early in their philosophical training. The arguments are apparently simple, but some of them, as I shall show, lead naturally on to thorny problems of modern philosophy. Another benefit that could be gained from reading the Euthyphro is that the reader may learn to be forewarned against some common fallacies and debating tricks in moral disputes.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   56 citations  
  • Plato’s Euthyphro.P. T. Geach - 1966 - The Monist 50 (3):369-382.
    The Euthyphro might well be given to undergraduates to read early in their philosophical training. The arguments are apparently simple, but some of them, as I shall show, lead naturally on to thorny problems of modern philosophy. Another benefit that could be gained from reading the Euthyphro is that the reader may learn to be forewarned against some common fallacies and debating tricks in moral disputes.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   43 citations  
  • Michael Dummett, Frege: Philosophy of Language. [REVIEW]Hidé Ishiguro - 1974 - Philosophy 49 (190):438-442.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   506 citations  
  • Causality and Explanation.Phil Dowe - 2000 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 51 (1):165-174.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Euthyphro's Thesis Revisited.Panos Dimas - 2006 - Phronesis 51 (1):1-28.
    It has been an interpretative dogma to condemn Euthyphro's attempt to account for piety in terms of the gods' wishes as one totally repudiated by Socrates, and in itself untenable. Still at 15c8-9 Socrates expresses some scepticism about whether his refutation of Euthyphro's original account of piety in terms of what the gods love has established that it must be abandoned altogether. He then goes on to say that he and Euthyphro ought to investigate again (πάλιν σ[unrepresentable symbol]επτέον), from the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Classical Philosophy: A Contemporary Introduction.Christopher John Shields - 2003 - New York: Routledge.
    Classical Philosophy is a comprehensive examination of early philosophy from the presocratics through to Aristotle. The aim of the book is to provide an explanation and analysis of the ideas that flourished at this time and considers their relevance both to the historical development of philosophy and to contemporary philosophy today. From these ideas we can see the roots of arguments in metaphysics, epistemology, ethics and political philosophy. The book is arranged in four parts by thinker and covers: The Presocratics (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Frege: Philosophy of Language.Michael Dummett - 1973 - London: Duckworth.
    This highly acclaimed book is a major contribution to the philosophy of language as well as a systematic interpretation of Frege, indisputably the father of ...
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   841 citations  
  • A Brief History of Western Philosophy.Anthony Kenny - 1998 - Malden, Mass.: Wiley-Blackwell.
    Spanning 2,500 years of thought, this superb volume provides essential coverage of the most influential philosophers of the Western world, including Socrates, ...
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Studies in the way of words.Herbert Paul Grice - 1989 - Cambridge: Harvard University Press.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   962 citations  
  • Modern logic: a text in elementary symbolic logic.Graeme Forbes - 1994 - New York: Oxford University Press.
    Filling the need for an accessible, carefully structured introductory text in symbolic logic, Modern Logic has many features designed to improve students' comprehension of the subject, including a proof system that is the same as the award-winning computer program MacLogic, and a special appendix that shows how to use MacLogic as a teaching aid. There are graded exercises at the end of each chapter--more than 900 in all--with selected answers at the end of the book. Unlike competing texts, Modern Logic (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   22 citations  
  • Plato's Introduction of Forms.R. M. Dancy - 2004 - New York: Cambridge University Press.
    Scholars of Plato are divided between those who emphasize the literature of the dialogues and those who emphasize the argument of the dialogues, and between those who see a development in the thought of the dialogues and those who do not. In this important book Russell Dancy focuses on the arguments and defends a developmental picture. He explains the Theory of Forms of the Phaedo and Symposium as an outgrowth of the quest for definitions canvassed in the Socratic dialogues, by (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   34 citations  
  • A Puzzle About 'because'.Benjamin Schnieder - 2010 - Logique Et Analyse 53.
    The essay is a partial investigation into the semantics of the explanatory connective ‘because’. After three independently plausible assumptions about ‘because’ are presented in some detail, it is shown how their interaction generates a puzzle about ‘because’, once they are combined with a common view on conceptual analysis. Four possible solutions to the puzzle are considered.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   47 citations  
  • Socratic Reasoning in the "Euthyphro".Albert Anderson - 1969 - Review of Metaphysics 22 (3):461 - 481.
    In the dialogue Plato portrays a confrontation between Euthyphro, a self-appointed expert on matters divine, who is about to charge his own father with impiety for alleged mistreatment and eventual death of a slave, and Socrates, already charged with impiety, who exploits the coincidence to elicit from Euthyphro certain complexities of the concept of 'piety'.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • To be is to be a value of a variable (or to be some values of some variables).George Boolos - 1984 - Journal of Philosophy 81 (8):430-449.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   276 citations  
  • Action.George Wilson - 2008 - Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
    If a person's head moves, she may or may not have moved her head, and, if she did move it, she may have actively performed the movement of her head or merely, by doing something else, caused a passive movement. And, if she performed the movement, she might have done so intentionally or not. This short array of contrasts (and others like them) has motivated questions about the nature, variety, and identity of action. Beyond the matter of her moving, when (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  • Dummett on Frege. [REVIEW]Leslie Stevenson - 1974 - Philosophical Quarterly 24 (97):349-359.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   235 citations  
  • Why-Questions.Sylvain Bromberger - 1966 - In Robert G. Colodny (ed.), Mind and Cosmos -- Essays in Contemporary Science and Philosophy. University of Pittsburgh Press. pp. 86--111.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   136 citations  
  • Plato's Euthyphro and the Earlier Theory of Forms.R. E. Allen - 1970 - Philosophy 46 (176):170-172.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations