Switch to: Citations

References in:

Nicolas Malebranche

Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (2008)

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. Nicolas Malebranche.Geneiviève Rodis-Lewis - 1963 - Zeitschrift für Philosophische Forschung 20 (2):336-338.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • La Liberté selon Malebranche.J. Laporte - 1938 - Revue de Métaphysique et de Morale 45:339-410.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • The Vision in God.Desmond Connell - 1972 - Revue Philosophique de la France Et de l'Etranger 162:215-218.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • A history of philosophy.Frederick C. Copleston - 1947 - New York, N.Y.: Image Books.
    Book 1. Volume I, Greece and Rome ; Volume II, Augustine to Scotus ; Volume III, Ockham to Suarez.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   84 citations  
  • The light of the soul: theories of ideas in Leibniz, Malebranche, and Descartes.Nicholas Jolley - 1990 - New York: Oxford University Press.
    The concept of an "idea" played a central role in 17th-century theories of mind and knowledge, but philosophers were divided over the nature of ideas. This book examines an important, but little-known, debate on this question in the work of Leibniz, Malebranche, and Descartes. Looking closely at the issues involved, as well as the particular context in which the debate took place, Jolley demonstrates that the debate has serious implications for a number of major topics in 17th-century philosophy.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   32 citations  
  • 8 Malebranche on Human Freedom.Elmar J. Kremer - 2000 - In Steven Nadler (ed.), The Cambridge companion to Malebranche. New York: Cambridge University Press. pp. 190.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Our Bodies, Our Selves: Malebranche on the Feelings of Embodiment.Colin Chamberlain - 2018 - Ergo: An Open Access Journal of Philosophy 5.
    Malebranche holds that the feeling of having a body comes in three main varieties. A perceiver sensorily experiences herself (1) as causally connected to her body, in so far as the senses represent the body as causing her sensory experiences and as uniquely responsive to her will, (2) as materially connected to her body, in so far as the senses represent the perceiver as a material being wrapped up with the body, and (3) as perspectivally connected to her body, in (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • ‘Let us imagine that God has made a miniature earth and sky’: Malebranche on the Body-Relativity of Visual Size.Colin Chamberlain - 2020 - Journal of the American Philosophical Association 6 (2):206-224.
    Malebranche holds that visual experience represents the size of objects relative to the perceiver's body and does not represent objects as having intrinsic or nonrelational spatial magnitudes. I argue that Malebranche's case for this body-relative thesis is more sophisticated than other commentators—most notably, Atherton and Simmons —have presented it. Malebranche's central argument relies on the possibility of perceptual variation with respect to size. He uses two thought experiments to show that perceivers of different sizes—namely, miniature people, giants, and typical human (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Cartesian Modes and The Simplicity of Mind.Galen Barry - 2014 - Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 96 (1):54-76.
    Malebranche argues that we lack a clear idea of the mind because we cannot, even in principle, derive all the possible modes of mind solely from the idea of thought. But we can, in principle, derive all the possible modes of body from the idea of extension. Therefore, there is epistemic asymmetry between our ideas of mind and body. I offer a defense of Descartes whereby he can assert that we have a clear idea of mind despite this asymmetry. I (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Occasionalism: causation among the Cartesians.Steven M. Nadler - 2011 - New York: Oxford University Press.
    These essays examine the philosophical, scientific, theological and religious themes and arguments of occasionalism, as well as its roots in medieval views on ...
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  • Malebranche et Leibniz.André Robinet (ed.) - 1955 - Paris,: J. Vrin.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Le cartésianisme de Malebranche.Ferdinand Alquié - 1974 - Paris,: J. Vrin.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Leibniz: general inquiries on the analysis of notions and truths.Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz - 2021 - Oxford: Oxford University Press. Edited by Massimo Mugnai & Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz.
    In General Inquiries on the Analysis of Notions and Truths, Leibniz articulates for the first time his favourite solution to the problem of contingency and displays the main features of his logical calculus. Leibniz composed the work in 1686, the same year in which he began to correspond with Arnauld and wrote the Discourse on Metaphysics. General Inquiries supplements these contemporary entries in Leibniz's philosophical oeuvre and demonstrates the intimate connection that links Leibniz's philosophy with the attempt to create a (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Malebranche.Andrew Pyle - 2003 - New York: Routledge.
    Nicolas Malebranche is one of the most important philosophers of the seventeenth century after Descartes. A pioneer of rationalism, he was one of the first to champion and to further Cartesian ideas. Andrew Pyle places Malebranche's work in the context of Descartes and other philosophers, and also in its relation to ideas about faith and reason. He examines the entirety of Malebranche's writings, including the famous The Search After Truth, which was admired and criticized by both Leibniz and Locke. Pyle (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  • Descartes, Malebranche, and the Crisis of Perception.Walter R. Ott - 2017 - Oxford: Oxford University Press.
    The seventeenth century witnesses the demise of two core doctrines in the theory of perception: naive realism about color, sound, and other sensible qualities and the empirical theory, drawn from Alhacen and Roger Bacon, which underwrote it. This created a problem for seventeenth century philosophers: how is that we use qualities such as color, feel, and sound to locate objects in the world, even though these qualities are not real? -/- Ejecting such sensible qualities from the mind-independent world at once (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Malebranche, the Quietists, and Freedom.Julie Walsh & Thomas M. Lennon - 2012 - British Journal for the History of Philosophy 20 (1):69 - 108.
    The Quietist affair at the end of the seventeenth century has much to teach us about theories of the will in the period. Although Bossuet and Fénelon are the names most famously associated with the debate over the Quietist conception of pure love, Malebranche and his erstwhile disciple Lamy were the ones who debated the deep philosophical issues involved. This paper sets the historical context of the debate, discusses the positions as well as the arguments for and against them, and (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Malebranche and the General Will of God.Eric Stencil - 2011 - British Journal for the History of Philosophy 19 (6):1107-1129.
    Central to Nicolas Malebranche’s theodicy is the distinction between general volitions and particular volitions. One of the fundamental claims of his theodicy is that although God created a world with suffering and evil, God does not will these things by particular volitions, but only by general volitions. Commentators disagree about how to interpret Malebranche’s distinction. According to the ‘general content’ interpretation, the difference between general volitions and particular volitions is a difference in content. General volitions have general laws as their (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • The Metaphysics of Rest in Descartes and Malebranche.Tad M. Schmaltz - 2015 - Res Philosophica 92 (1):21-40.
    I consider a somewhat obscure but important feature of Descartes’s physics that concerns the notion of the “force of rest.” Contrary to a prominent occasionalist interpretation of Descartes’s physics, I argue that Descartes himself attributes real forces to resting bodies. I also take his account of rest to conflict with the view that God conserves the world by “re-creating” it anew at each moment. I turn next to the role of rest in Malebranche. Malebranche takes Descartes to endorse his own (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Malebranche and Leibniz on the best of all possible worlds.Tad M. Schmaltz - 2010 - Southern Journal of Philosophy 48 (1):28-48.
    In this article I explore Leibniz's claim in the Theodicy that on the essential points Malebranche's theodicy "reduces to" his own view. This judgment may seem to be warranted given that both thinkers emphasize that evils are justified by the fact that they follow from the simple and uniform laws that govern that world which is worthy of divine creation. However, I argue that Leibniz's theodicy differs in several crucial respects from Malebranche's. I begin with a qualified endorsement of Charles (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Malebranche. [REVIEW]Tad M. Schmaltz - 2004 - Mind 113 (449):215-218.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Cartesian causation: body–body interaction, motion, and eternal truths.Tad M. Schmaltz - 2003 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 34 (4):737-762.
    There is considerable debate among scholars over whether Descartes allowed for genuine body–body interaction. I begin by considering Michael Della Rocca’s recent claim that Descartes accepted such interaction, and that his doctrine of the creation of the eternal truths indicates how this interaction could be acceptable to him. Though I agree that Descartes was inclined to accept real bodily causes of motion, I differ from Della Rocca in emphasizing that his ontology ultimately does not allow for them. This is not (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Descartes, Malebranche and Leibniz: conceptions of substance in arguments for the immateriality of the soul.Marleen Rozemond - 2016 - British Journal for the History of Philosophy 24 (5):836-857.
    ABSTRACTThe most prominent early modern argument against materialism is to be found in Descartes. Previously I had argued that this argument relies crucially on a robust conception of substance, according to which it has a single principal attribute of which all its other intrinsic qualities are modes. In the present paper I return to this claim. In Section 2, I address a question that is often raised about that conception of substance: its commitment to the idea that a substance has (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Malebranche on intelligible extension.Jasper Reid - 2003 - British Journal for the History of Philosophy 11 (4):581 – 608.
    This paper explores the ontology of Malebranche's notion of "intelligible extension", the archetypal divine idea of matter which he believed to be the immediate object of our own minds in all of our thoughts about corporeal things. Building on this account of its ontology, and through an examination of a form of isomorphism between intelligible extension and the created spatial world, the paper also attempts to explain the manner in which it could fulfill its epistemological role of representing all possible (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  • Malebranche: a study of a Cartesian system.Daisie Radner - 1978 - Assen: Van Gorcum.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • Causation, intentionality, and the case for occasionalism.Walter Ott - 2008 - Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie 90 (2):165-187.
    Despite their influence on later philosophers such as Hume, Malebranche's central arguments for occasionalism remain deeply puzzling. Both the famous ‘no necessary connection’ argument and what I call the epistemic argument include assumptions – e.g., that a true cause is logically necessarily connected to its effect – that seem unmotivated, even in their context. I argue that a proper understanding of late scholastic views lets us see why Malebranche would make this assumption. Both arguments turn on the claim that a (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Self-knowledge in Descartes and Malebranche.Lawrence Nolan & John Whipple - 2005 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 43 (1):55-81.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Journal of the History of Philosophy 43.1 (2005) 55-81 [Access article in PDF] Self-Knowledge in Descartes and Malebranche Lawrence Nolan John Whipple 1. Introduction Descartes's notorious claim that mind is better known than body has been the target of repeated criticisms, but none appears more challenging than that of his intellectual heir Nicolas Malebranche.1 Whereas other critics—especially twentieth-century philosophers eager to use Descartes as their whipping boy—have often been (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Occasionalism and general will in Malebranche.Steven M. Nadler - 1993 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 31 (1):31-47.
    This paper examines a common misreading of the mechanics of Malebranche's doctrine of divine causal agency, occasionalism, and its roots in a related misreading of Malebranche's theories. God, contrary to this misreading, is for Malebranche constantly and actively causally engaged in the world, and does not just establish certain laws of nature. The key is in understanding just what Malebranche means by general volitions'.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  • Descartes and Malebranche on thought, sensation and the nature of the mind.Antonia LoLordo - 2005 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 43 (4):387-402.
    : Malebranche famously objects to Descartes' argument that the nature of the mind is better known than the nature of body as follows: if we had an idea of the mind's nature we would know the possible range of modes of the mind, including the sensory modes, but we do not know those modes and thus can't have an idea of the mind's nature. I argue that Malebranche's objections are readily answerable from within the Cartesian system. This argument involves examining (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Passive Natures and No Representations.Sukjae Lee - 2007 - The Harvard Review of Philosophy 15 (1):72-91.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Occasionalism and efficacious laws in Malebranche.Nicholas Jolley - 2002 - Midwest Studies in Philosophy 26 (1):245–257.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Malebranche on the passions: Biology, morality and the fall.Sean Greenberg - 2010 - British Journal for the History of Philosophy 18 (2):191 – 207.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Malebranche and Ideas.Treatise on Nature and Grace.Lisa Downing, Steven Nadler, Nicolas Malebranche & Patrick Riley - 1995 - Philosophical Review 104 (1):122.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Occasionalismus. Theorien der Kausalität im arabisch-islamischen und im europäischen Denken.Dominik Perler & Ulrich Rudolph - 2000 - Göttingen, Deutschland: Vandenhoeck & Ruprecht. Edited by Ulrich Rudolph.
    Thomas von Aquin reagierte im 13. Jahrhundert als erster europäischer Theologe auf den Occasionalismus, der sich im arabisch-islamischen Denken vom 8. bis zum 12. Jahrhundert entwickelte, und begann damit die bis in das 17. Jahrhundert fortdauernde Auseinandersetzung mit diesem Thema. Die Autoren stellen in chronologischer Reihenfolge die gesamte arabisch-islamische und europäische Diskussion vor.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • Nicolas Malebranche.Vere Claiborne Chappell (ed.) - 1992 - New York: Garland.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • La volonté selon Malebranche.Ginette Dreyfus - 1958 - Vrin.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Deux Cartesiens: la polemique entre Antoine Arnauld et Nicolas Malebranche.Denis Moreau - 1999 - Paris: Vrin.
    De 1683 a 1694, Antoine Arnauld et Nicolas Malebranche, anciens amis et pretres que leur interet pour Descartes, leur reverence pour Augustin et leur commune inquietude face au libertinage semblaient pourtant destiner a s'entendre, polemiquerent violemment. En insistant sur l'aspect philosophique de ces debats, cet ouvrage propose la premiere interpretation d'ensemble de cette celebre confrontation. Y a-t-il de serieuses raisons philosophiques au desaccord entre Arnauld et Malebranche? Leur determination permet-elle d'eclairer certains aspects du malebranchisme? Existe-t-il une philosophie d'Antoine Arnauld et (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Bibliographia Malebranchiana: A Critical Guide to the Malebranche Literature Into 1989.Patricia Easton, Thomas M. Lennon & Gregor Sebba - 1992 - Southern Illinois University.
    This bibliography consists of 936 numbered entries, with references to a far greater number of works. The first part covers works by Malebranche and consists of six sections on his collected works, selections from his works, his individual works, translations of his works, his correspondence, and the controversies into which he entered. The second part deals with works on Malebranche and consists of other bibliographical sources, biographical references, and studies. As a critical bibliography, this book contains not only references to (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Nicholas Malebranche: His Philosophical Critics and Successors.Stuart Brown (ed.) - 1991 - Assen: Van Gorcum.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Nicolas Malebranche: Freedom in an Occasionalist World.Susan Peppers-Bates - 2009 - Continuum.
    Malebranche's metaphysics and the problem of human freedom -- God, order, and general volitions -- Arnauld and Malebranche on the power of the human intellect -- The cognitive faculties and the divine ideas -- Malebranche on free will and imminent causation.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Malebranche et le quiétisme.Y. de Montcheuil - 1950 - Revue Philosophique de la France Et de l'Etranger 140 (3):212-214.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Occasionalism, Human Freedom, and Consent in Malebranche: 'Things that Undermine Each Other'?Sean Greenberg - 2016 - Oxford Studies in Early Modern Philosophy 7:151-186.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Things that Undermine Each Other': Occasionalism, Freedom, and Attention in Malebranche.Sean Greenberg - 2008 - In Daniel Garber & Steven Nadler (eds.), Oxford Studies in Early Modern Philosophy Volume Iv. Oxford University Press.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • The Most Dangerous Error: Malebranche on the Experience of Causation.Colin Chamberlain - 2021 - Philosophers' Imprint 21 (10).
    Do the senses represent causation? Many commentators read Nicolas Malebranche as anticipating David Hume’s negative answer to this question. I disagree with this assessment. When a yellow billiard ball strikes a red billiard ball, Malebranche holds that we see the yellow ball as causing the red ball to move. Given Malebranche’s occasionalism, he insists that the visual experience of causal interaction is illusory. Nevertheless, Malebranche holds that the senses represent finite things as causally efficacious. This experience of creaturely causality explains (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Malebranche and British Philosophy.Charles Mccracken - 1983 - Revue Philosophique de la France Et de l'Etranger 173 (4):467-468.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   25 citations  
  • Occasionalism and strict mechanism: Malebranche, Berkeley, fontenelle.Lisa Downing - 2005 - In Christia Mercer (ed.), Early Modern Philosophy: Mind, Matter, and Metaphysics. Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press. pp. 206-230.
    The rich connections between metaphysics and natural philosophy in the early modern period have been widely acknowledged and productively mined, thanks in no small part to the work of Margaret Wilson, whose book, Descartes, served as an inspirational example for a generation of scholars. The task of this paper is to investigate one particular such connection, namely, the relation between occasionalist metaphysics and strict mechanism. My focus will be on the work of Nicholas Malebranche, the most influential Cartesian philosopher after (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • The Cambridge Companion to Malebranche.Steven Nadler - 2002 - Philosophical Quarterly 52 (207):258-261.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • La vocation de Malebranche.H. Gouhier - 1928 - Revue Philosophique de la France Et de l'Etranger 106:152-153.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Malebranche, Freedom, and the Divided Mind.Julie Walsh - 2015 - In P. Easton & K. Smith (eds.), Gods and Giants in Early Modern Philosophy. Brill. pp. 194-216.
    In this paper I argue that according to Malebranche mental attention is the corrective to epistemic error and moral lapse and constitutes the essence of human freedom. Moreover, I show how this conception of human freedom is both morally significant and compatible with occasionalism. By attending to four distinctions made by Malebranche throughout his writings we can begin to understand first, what it means for human beings to exercise their freedom in a way that has some meaningful consequence, and second, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Etendue et Psychologie chez Malebranche.M. Guéroult - 1941 - Revue de Métaphysique et de Morale 48 (3):239-239.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation