Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. The IRB is not a data and safety monitoring board.Elizabeth Bankert & Robert Amdur - 2000 - IRB: Ethics & Human Research 22 (6):9.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Recipient design in tacit communication.Sarah E. Newman-Norlund, Matthijs L. Noordzij, Roger D. Newman-Norlund, Inge A. C. Volman, Jan Peter de Ruiter, Peter Hagoort & Ivan Toni - 2009 - Cognition 111 (1):46-54.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Declaration of Helsinki. Ethical Principles for Medical Research Involving Human Subjects.World Medical Association - 2009 - Jahrbuch für Wissenschaft Und Ethik 14 (1):233-238.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   313 citations  
  • Phase I cancer trials: A collusion of misunderstanding.Matthew Miller - 2000 - Hastings Center Report 30 (4):34-43.
    Physician‐investigators face the daunting task of enrolling desperate patients into Phase I cancer trials that are not meant to be therapeutic. Patients doggedly regard the trials as therapeutic, and researchers tend to collaborate in their confusion by glossing the trials’ true purposes and noting the occasional benefit that subjects accidentally receive. The disparity between hope and fact must be redressed by degrees, from many angles at once.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   30 citations  
  • Bounded ethicality as a psychological barrier to recognizing conflicts of interest.Dolly Chugh, Max H. Bazerman & Mahzarin R. Banaji - 2005 - In Don A. Moore (ed.), Conflicts of interest: challenges and solutions in business, law, medicine, and public policy. New York: Cambridge University Press.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   46 citations  
  • Are physicians obligated always to act in the patient's best interests?D. Wendler - 2010 - Journal of Medical Ethics 36 (2):66-70.
    The principle that physicians should always act in the best interests of the present patient is widely endorsed. At the same time, and often within the same document, it is recognised that there are appropriate exceptions to this principle. Unfortunately, little, if any, guidance is provided regarding which exceptions are appropriate and how they should be handled. These circumstances might be tenable if the appropriate exceptions were rare. Yet, evaluation of the literature reveals that there are numerous exceptions, several of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   23 citations  
  • The Physician/Investigator's Obligation to Patients Participating in Research: The Case of Placebo Controlled Trials.Kathleen Cranley Glass & Duff Waring - 2005 - Journal of Law, Medicine and Ethics 33 (3):575-585.
    Some authors argue that the ethics of medical care and the ethics of research differ, and that it is a mistake to conflate the two. They propose “that medical research and medical treatment are two distinct forms of activities, governed by different ethical principles.” This raises the question of whether physicians who are also clinical investigators may separate their role as physician from that of researcher when they are involved in clinical trials, thereby avoiding the obligations required in the physician-patient (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • What the doctor didn't say: the hidden truth about medical research.Jerry Menikoff - 2006 - New York: Oxford University Press. Edited by Edward P. Richards.
    Most people know precious little about the risks and benefits of participating in a clinical trial--a medical research study involving some innovative treatment for a medical problem. Yet millions of people each year participate anyway. Patients at Risk explains the reality: that our current system intentionally hides much of the information people need to make the right choice about whether to participate. Witness the following scenarios: -Hundreds of patients with colon cancer undergo a new form of keyhole surgery at leading (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  • (1 other version)Ethics and regulation of clinical research.Robert J. Levine - 1986 - Baltimore: Urban & Schwarzenberg.
    In this book, Dr. Robert J. Levine reviews federal regulations, ethical analysis, and case studies in an attempt to answer these questions.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   122 citations  
  • Clinical equipoise and the incoherence of research ethics.Franklin G. Miller & Howard Brody - 2007 - Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 32 (2):151 – 165.
    The doctrine of clinical equipoise is appealing because it appears to permit physicians to maintain their therapeutic obligation to offer optimal medical care to patients while conducting randomized controlled trials (RCTs). The appearance, however, is deceptive. In this article we argue that clinical equipoise is defective and incoherent in multiple ways. First, it conflates the sound methodological principle that RCTs should begin with an honest null hypothesis with the questionable ethical norm that participants in these trials should never be randomized (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  • The clinician-investigator: Unavoidable but manageable tension.Howard Brody & Franklin G. Miller - 2003 - Kennedy Institute of Ethics Journal 13 (4):329-346.
    : The "difference position" holds that clinical research and therapeutic medical practice are sufficiently distinct activities to require different ethical rules and principles. The "similarity position" holds instead that clinical investigators ought to be bound by the same fundamental principles that govern therapeutic medicine—specifically, a duty to provide the optimal therapeutic benefit to each patient or subject. Some defenders of the similarity position defend it because of the overlap between the role of attending physician and the role of investigator in (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   45 citations  
  • Re-evaluating the therapeutic misconception: Response to Miller and Joffe.Paul S. Appelbaum & Charles W. Lidz - 2006 - Kennedy Institute of Ethics Journal 16 (4):367-373.
    : Responding to the paper by Miller and Joffe, we review the development of the concept of therapeutic misconception (TM). Our concerns about TM's impact on informed consent do not derive from the belief that research subjects have poorer outcomes than persons receiving ordinary clinical care. Rather, we believe that subjects with TM cannot give an adequate informed consent to research participation, which harms their dignitary interests and their abilities to make meaningful decisions. Ironically, Miller and Joffe's approach ends up (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • A Closer Look at the Bad Deal Trial: Beyond Clinical Equipoise.Lynn A. Jansen - 2005 - Hastings Center Report 35 (5):29.
    Some commentators have recently proposed that “clinical equipoise,” although widely accepted, is not necessary for morally acceptable research on human subjects. If this concept is rejected, however, we may find that trials not in the best medical interests of their subjects—”bad deal trials”—could be justified. To avoid exploiting participants, we must find a way to distribute the risks fairly, even if it means embracing radical changes in the way clinical research is conducted.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Principles of Biomedical Ethics.Ezekiel J. Emanuel, Tom L. Beauchamp & James F. Childress - 1995 - Hastings Center Report 25 (4):37.
    Book reviewed in this article: Principles of Biomedical Ethics. By Tom L. Beauchamp and James F. Childress.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2264 citations  
  • (1 other version)Judgment under Uncertainty: Heuristics and Biases.Amos Tversky & Daniel Kahneman - 1974 - Science 185 (4157):1124-1131.
    This article described three heuristics that are employed in making judgements under uncertainty: representativeness, which is usually employed when people are asked to judge the probability that an object or event A belongs to class or process B; availability of instances or scenarios, which is often employed when people are asked to assess the frequency of a class or the plausibility of a particular development; and adjustment from an anchor, which is usually employed in numerical prediction when a relevant value (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1709 citations  
  • Evidence, Belief, and Action: The Failure of Equipoise to Resolve the Ethical Tension in the Randomized Clinical Trial.Deborah Hellman - 2002 - Journal of Law, Medicine and Ethics 30 (3):375-380.
    Clinical research employing the randomized clinical trial has, traditionally, been understood to pose an ethical dilemma. On the one hand, each patient ought to get the treatment that best meets her needs, as judged by the patient in consultation with her doctor. On the other hand, the method most helpful to advancing our understanding about what treatments are indeed best able to meet patient needs is the randomized trial, which necessitates that each patient's care is decided not by physician judgment (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • The Clinical Investigator as Fiduciary: Discarding a Misguided Idea.E. Haavi Morreim - 2005 - Journal of Law, Medicine and Ethics 33 (3):586-598.
    One of the most important questions in the ethics of human clinical research asks what obligations investigators owe the people who enroll in their studies. Research differs in many ways from standard care - the added uncertainties, for instance, and the nontherapeutic interventions such as diagnostic tests whose only purpose is to measure the effects of the research intervention. Hence arises the question whether a physician engaged in clinical research has the same obligations toward research subjects that he owes his (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   27 citations  
  • """ Therapeutic misconception" and" recruiting doublespeak" in the informed consent process.Mark Hochhauser - 2001 - IRB: Ethics & Human Research 24 (1):11-12.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • ""By any other name: the many iterations of" patient advocate" in clinical research.E. Haavi Morreim - 2004 - IRB: Ethics & Human Research 26 (6):1.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Taking a lesson from the lawyers: Defining and addressing conflict of interest.E. Haavi Morreim - 2011 - American Journal of Bioethics 11 (1):33 - 34.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • (1 other version)Defining and Describing Benefit Appropriately in Clinical Trials.Nancy M. P. King - 2000 - Journal of Law, Medicine and Ethics 28 (4):332-343.
    Institutional review boards and investigators are used to talking about risks of harm. Both low risks of great harm and high risks of small harm must be disclosed to prospective subjects and should be explained and categorized in ways that help potential subjects to understand and weigh them appropriately. Everyone on an IRB has probably spent time at meetings arguing over whether a three-page bulleted list of risk description is helpful or overkill for prospective subjects. Yet only a small fraction (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   67 citations  
  • “Damaged humanity”: The call for a patient-centered medical ethic in the managed care era.Larry R. Churchill - 1997 - Theoretical Medicine and Bioethics 18 (1-2):113-126.
    Edmund Pellegrino claims that medical ethics must be derived from a perception of the patient's damaged humanity, rather than from the self-imposed duties of professionals. This essay explores the meaning and examines the challenges to this patient-centered ethic. Social scientific and bioethical interpretations of medicine constitute one kind of challenge. A more pervasive challenge is the ascendancy of managed care, and especially investor-owned, for-profit managed care. A list of questions addressed to patients, physicians and organizations is offered as one means (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Is it Really All about the Money? Reconsidering Non-Financial Interests in Medical Research.Richard S. Saver - 2012 - Journal of Law, Medicine and Ethics 40 (3):467-481.
    Conflicts of interest have been reduced to financial conflicts. The National Institutes of Health’s new rules for managing conflicts of interest in medical research, the first major change to the regulations in over 15 years, address only financial ties. Although several commentators urged that the regulations also cover non-financial interests, the Department of Health and Human Services declined to do so. Similarly, the Institute of Medicine’s influential 2009 Conflict of Interest Report focuses almost exclusively on financial conflicts. Institutional policies at (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • (1 other version)The Social Transformation of American Medicine.Paul Starr - 1984 - Science and Society 48 (1):116-118.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   179 citations  
  • The ubiquity and utility of the therapeutic misconception.Rebecca Dresser - 2002 - Social Philosophy and Policy 19 (2):271-294.
    The term “therapeutic misconception” was coined in 1982 by Paul Appelbaum, Loren Roth, and Charles Lidz. Appelbaum and his colleagues interviewed participants in several psychiatric studies, including a drug trial with a placebo control arm. Appelbaum's group found that many people were unaware of the differences between participating in a study and receiving treatment in the clinical setting. Rather than understanding these differences, study participants tended to believe that therapy and research were governed by the same primary goal: to advance (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   22 citations