Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. Matter, form, and individuation.Jeffrey E. Brower - 2011 - In Brian Davies & Eleonore Stump (eds.), The Oxford handbook of Aquinas. New York: Oxford University Press. pp. 85-103.
    Few notions are more central to Aquinas’s thought than those of matter and form. Although he invokes these notions in a number of different contexts, and puts them to a number of different uses, he always assumes that in their primary or basic sense they are correlative both with each other and with the notion of a “hylomorphic compound”—that is, a compound of matter (hyle) and form (morphe). Thus, matter is an entity that can have form, form is an entity (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Aquinas on the Problem of Universals.Jeffrey E. Brower - 2016 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 92 (2):715-735.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Aquinas on the Individuation of Substances.Jeffrey E. Brower - 2017 - Oxford Studies in Medieval Philosophy 5 (1).
    Aquinas has much to say about individuation over the course of his career. Although certain aspects of his views appear to undergo development, there is one aspect that remains constant throughout—namely, his commitment to assigning both prime matter and quantity an essential role in the individuation of substances. This paper examines the vexed issue of how either prime matter or quantity, as Aquinas understands them, could have any role to play in this context. In the course of doing so, the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Accidental sameness in Aristotle.Frank A. Lewis - 1982 - Philosophical Studies 42 (1):1 - 36.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   28 citations  
  • Neo-Aristotelian Plenitude.Ross Inman - 2014 - Philosophical Studies 168 (3):583-597.
    Plenitude, roughly, the thesis that for any non-empty region of spacetime there is a material object that is exactly located at that region, is often thought to be part and parcel of the standard Lewisian package in the metaphysics of persistence. While the wedding of plentitude and Lewisian four-dimensionalism is a natural one indeed, there are a hand-full of dissenters who argue against the notion that Lewisian four-dimensionalism has exclusive rights to plentitude. These ‘promiscuous’ three-dimensionalists argue that a temporalized version (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   22 citations  
  • Aquinas on Continuity and Identity.Christopher Hughes - 1997 - Medieval Philosophy & Theology 6 (1):93-108.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Parts, Wholes, and Presence by Power A Response to Gordon P. Barnes.Michael Hector Storck - 2008 - Review of Metaphysics 62 (1):45-59.
    Gordon P. Barnes has recently argued that presence by power is inadequate as an explanation of the way elements are present in complex bodies, and that it would be better to explain the elements’ presence by claiming that simpler substances—carbon atoms, for example—are actually and substantially present in living things. In order to address his arguments, this paper begins by briefly presenting St. Thomas’s understanding of presence by power, and then argues that Barnes’s proposal—that there is a multiplicity of substantial (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Mind and Hylomorphism.Robert Pasnau - 2012 - In John Marenbon (ed.), The Oxford Handbook to Medieval Philosophy. Oxford University Press.
    For later medieval philosophers, writing under the influence of Aristotle’s natural philosophy and metaphysics, the human soul plays two quite different roles, serving as both a substantial form and a mind. To ask the natural question of why we need a soul at all – why we might not instead simply be a body, a material thing – therefore requires considering two very different sets of issues. The first set of issues is metaphysical, and revolves around the central question of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Groundwork for a Thomistic account of contemporary property roles.Lindsay Kathryn Cleveland - 2018 - Dissertation, Baylor University
    Chapter one serves as an introduction to the whole dissertation. In it I explain why I think philosophers should pursue a systematic, pluralist account of contemporary property roles and consider Thomistic explanations of such roles. I also summarize in more detail the chapters that make up this dissertation. In chapter two I explain the metaphysical and semantic roles that properties are thought to play and briefly introduce the main contemporary accounts of properties in terms of which property roles they address (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Form and Matter.Robert Pasnau - 2009 - In The Cambridge History of Medieval Philosophy. Cambridge University Press.
    The first unquestionably big idea in the history of philosophy was the idea of form. The idea of course belonged to Plato, and was then domesticated at the hands of Aristotle, who paired form with matter as the two chief principles of his metaphysics and natural philosophy. In the medieval period, it was Aristotle’s conception of form and matter that generally dominated. This was true for both the Islamic and the Christian tradition, once the entire Aristotelian corpus became available. For (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • Accidental unities.Gareth B. Matthews - 1982 - In M. Schofield & M. C. Nussbaum (eds.), Language and Logos. Cambridge University Press. pp. 223--240.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   40 citations  
  • Aristotle: Metaphysics.Michael Loux - forthcoming - Ancient Philosophy.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   20 citations  
  • Elemental virtual presence in St. Thomas.Christopher Decaen - 2000 - The Thomist 64 (2):271-300.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Aquinas on Nature, Hypostasis, and the Metaphysics of the Incarnation.Richard Cross - 1996 - The Thomist 60 (2):171 - 202.
    Aquinas distinguishes four types of part included in a hypostasis (’suppositum’): (1) kind-nature; (2) individuating feature(s); (3) accidents; (4) concrete parts. (1) - (3) in some sense contribute ’esse’ to the ’suppositum’. Usually Aquinas holds that Christ’s human nature does not contribute ’esse’ to its divine ’suppositum’, since it is analogous to a concrete part of its ’suppositum’. This effectively commits Aquinas to the Monophysite heresy. In ’De Unione’ Aquinas argues instead that Christ’s human nature contributes ’secondary ’esse‘ to its (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Aquinas on Continuity and Identity.Christopher Hughes - 1997 - Journal of Nietzsche Studies 6 (93):93-108.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations