Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. Pretense and representation: The origins of "theory of mind.".Alan M. Leslie - 1987 - Psychological Review 94 (4):412-426.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   590 citations  
  • Neurocomputational Perspective.P. M. Churchland - 1993 - Behavior and Philosophy 20 (2):75-88.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   123 citations  
  • Does the autistic child have a “theory of mind”?Simon Baron-Cohen, Alan M. Leslie & Uta Frith - 1985 - Cognition 21 (1):37-46.
    We use a new model of metarepresentational development to predict a cognitive deficit which could explain a crucial component of the social impairment in childhood autism. One of the manifestations of a basic metarepresentational capacity is a ‘ theory of mind ’. We have reason to believe that autistic children lack such a ‘ theory ’. If this were so, then they would be unable to impute beliefs to others and to predict their behaviour. This hypothesis was tested using Wimmer (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   648 citations  
  • (4 other versions)Connectionism, eliminativism and the future of folk psychology.William Ramsey, Stephen Stich & Joseph Garon - 1990 - Philosophical Perspectives 4:499-533.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   47 citations  
  • Psychologism, folk psychology and one's own case.Richard Montgomery - 1987 - Journal for the Theory of Social Behaviour 17 (2):195–218.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • The appeal to tacit knowledge in psychological explanation.Jerry A. Fodor - 1968 - Journal of Philosophy 65 (October):627-40.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   185 citations  
  • (1 other version)Replication and functionalism.Jane Heal - 1986 - In Jeremy Butterfield (ed.), Language, mind and logic. New York: Cambridge University Press. pp. 135--150.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   161 citations  
  • Interpretation psychologized.Alvin I. Goldman - 1989 - Mind and Language 4 (3):161-85.
    The aim of this paper is to study interpretation, specifically, to work toward an account of interpretation that seems descriptively and explanatorily correct. No account of interpretation can be philosophically helpful, I submit, if it is incompatible with a correct account of what people actually do when they interpret others. My question, then, is: how does the (naive) interpreter arrive at his/her judgments about the mental attitudes of others? Philosophers who have addressed this question have not, in my view, been (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   365 citations  
  • Folk psychology as simulation.Robert M. Gordon - 1986 - Mind and Language 1 (2):158-71.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   502 citations  
  • Physical symbol systems.Allen Newell - 1980 - Cognitive Science 4 (2):135-83.
    On the occasion of a first conference on Cognitive Science, it seems appropriate to review the basis of common understanding between the various disciplines. In my estimate, the most fundamental contribution so far of artificial intelligence and computer science to the joint enterprise of cognitive science has been the notion of a physical symbol system, i.e., the concept of a broad class of systems capable of having and manipulating symbols, yet realizable in the physical universe. The notion of symbol so (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   487 citations  
  • (4 other versions)Connectionism, eliminativism, and the future of folk psychology.William Ramsey, Stephen P. Stich & J. Garon - 1991 - In William Ramsey, Stephen P. Stich & D. M. Rumelhart (eds.), Philosophy and Connectionist Theory. Hillsdale, N.J.: Lawrence Erlbaum. pp. 499-533.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   88 citations  
  • Beliefs and subdoxastic states.Stephen P. Stich - 1978 - Philosophy of Science 45 (December):499-518.
    It is argued that the intuitively sanctioned distinction between beliefs and non-belief states that play a role in the proximate causal history of beliefs is a distinction worth preserving in cognitive psychology. The intuitive distinction is argued to rest on a pair of features exhibited by beliefs but not by subdoxastic states. These are access to consciousness and inferential integration. Harman's view, which denies the distinction between beliefs and subdoxastic states, is discussed and criticized.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   314 citations  
  • Form, function and feel.William Lycan - 1981 - Journal of Philosophy 78 (January):24-50.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   242 citations  
  • The Second Naive Physics Manifesto.P. J. Hayes - 1985 - In Jerry R. Hobbs & Robert C. Moore (eds.), Formal Theories of the Commonsense World. Intellect Books.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   117 citations  
  • The Language of Thought.J. A. Fodor - 1978 - Critica 10 (28):140-143.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1455 citations  
  • (2 other versions)Vision: Variations on Some Berkeleian Themes.Robert Schwartz & David Marr - 1985 - Philosophical Review 94 (3):411.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   755 citations  
  • (1 other version)Eliminative Materialism and the Propositional Attitudes.Paul M. Churchland - 1981 - Journal of Philosophy 78 (2):67-90.
    Eliminative materialism is the thesis that our common-sense conception of psychological phenomena constitutes a radically false theory, a theory so fundamentally defective that both the principles and the ontology of that theory will eventually be displaced, rather than smoothly reduced, by completed neuroscience. Our mutual understanding and even our introspection may then be reconstituted within the conceptual framework of completed neuroscience, a theory we may expect to be more powerful by far than the common-sense psychology it displaces, and more substantially (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   896 citations  
  • Content and Consciousness.D. C. Dennett - 1969 - Journal of Philosophy 69 (18):604-604.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   324 citations  
  • Explanation and Empathy.Arthur Ripstein - 1987 - Review of Metaphysics 40 (3):465 - 482.
    I WISH to defend the claim that imagining what it would be like to be in "someone else's shoes" can serve to explain that person's actions. This commonsense view has considerable plausibility, but requires clarification to be philosophically defensible; discussions of explanation often assume that understanding requires a theory of the thing understood. If understanding requires a theory, then however much imagining what it would be like to be in another person's situation might sooth one's curiosity, it cannot provide real (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • The specificity of language skills.Jerry A. Fodor, Thomas G. Bever & Mary Garrett - 1974 - In Jerry Fodor, Bever A., Garrett T. G. & F. M. (eds.), The Psychology of Language: An Introduction to Psycholinguistics and Generative Grammar. Mcgraw-Hill.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   265 citations  
  • (1 other version)The medium and the message in mental imagery: A theory.Stephen M. Kosslyn - 1981 - In Ned Joel Block (ed.), Imagery. MIT Press.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   38 citations  
  • (4 other versions)Connectionism, eliminativism and the future of folk psychology.William Ramsey, Stephen P. Stich & J. Garon - 1991 - In William Ramsey, Stephen P. Stich & D. M. Rumelhart (eds.), Philosophy and Connectionist Theory. Hillsdale, N.J.: Lawrence Erlbaum. pp. 499-533.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   34 citations