Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. Deontic logic and the role of freedom in moral deliberation.Richmond H. Thomason - 1981 - In Risto Hilpinen (ed.), New Studies in Deontic Logic: Norms, Actions, and the Foundations of Ethics. Dordrecht, Netherland: Wiley-Blackwell. pp. 177--186.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   33 citations  
  • The Concept of Moral Obligation.Lou Goble - 1996 - Philosophical and Phenomenological Research 60 (1):242-244.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   99 citations  
  • Ought to Have' and 'Could Have.Walter Sinnott-Armstrong - 1985 - Analysis 45 (1):44 - 48.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • `Ought' conversationally implies `can'.Walter Sinnott-Armstrong - 1984 - Philosophical Review 93 (2):249-261.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   93 citations  
  • Moral dilemmas.Walter Sinnott-Armstrong - 1988 - New York, NY, USA: Blackwell.
    A strong tradition in philosophy denies the possibility of moral dilemmas. Recently, several philosophers reversed this tradition. In this dissertation, I clarify some fundamental issues in this debate, argue for the possibility of moral dilemmas, and determine some implications of this possibility. ;In chapter I, I define moral dilemmas roughly as situations where an agent morally ought to adopt each of two alternatives but cannot adopt both. Moral dilemmas are resolvable if and only if one of the moral oughts overrides (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   100 citations  
  • Moral Dilemmas.Philip L. Quinn - 1991 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 51 (3):693-697.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • Ought-implies-can: Erasmus Luther and R.m. Hare.Charles R. Pigden - 1990 - Sophia 29 (1):2-30.
    l. There is an antinomy in Hare's thought between Ought-Implies-Can and No-Indicatives-from-Imperatives. It cannot be resolved by drawing a distinction between implication and entailment. 2. Luther resolved this antinomy in the l6th century, but to understand his solution, we need to understand his problem. He thought the necessity of Divine foreknowledge removed contingency from human acts, thus making it impossible for sinners to do otherwise than sin. 3. Erasmus objected (on behalf of Free Will) that this violates Ought-Implies-Can which he (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Two Sorts of 'Ought's.I. L. Humberstone - 1971 - Analysis 32 (1):8 - 11.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   23 citations  
  • The Causal Theory of Perception.H. P. Grice & Alan R. White - 1961 - Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 35 (1):121-168.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   237 citations  
  • Studies in the Way of Words.D. E. Over - 1990 - Philosophical Quarterly 40 (160):393-395.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   431 citations  
  • Dated rightness and moral imperfection.Holly S. Goldman - 1976 - Philosophical Review 85 (4):449-487.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   61 citations  
  • Review of James W. Forrester: Why You Should: The Pragmatics of Deontic Speech.[REVIEW]William Tolhurst - 1990 - Ethics 100 (4):888-888.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • The Concept of Moral Obligation.Michael J. Zimmerman - 1996 - New York: Cambridge University Press.
    The principal aim of this book is to develop and defend an analysis of the concept of moral obligation. The analysis is neutral regarding competing substantive theories of obligation, whether consequentialist or deontological in character. What it seeks to do is generate solutions to a range of philosophical problems concerning obligation and its application. Amongst these problems are deontic paradoxes, the supersession of obligation, conditional obligation, prima facie obligation, actualism and possibilism, dilemmas, supererogation, and cooperation. By virtue of its normative (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   136 citations  
  • Studies in the way of words.Herbert Paul Grice - 1989 - Cambridge: Harvard University Press.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   962 citations  
  • The Causal Theory of Perception.H. P. Grice - 1961 - In Sven Bernecker & Fred I. Dretske (eds.), Knowledge: Readings in Contemporary Epistemology. Oxford University Press.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   132 citations  
  • Ought Does Not Imply Can.Paul Saka - 2000 - American Philosophical Quarterly 37 (2):93 - 105.
    Moral philosophers widely believe that it is a part of the MEANING of 'ought' statements that they imply 'can' statements. To this thesis I offer three challenges, and then I conclude on a broader methodological note. (1) Epistemological Modal Argument: for all we know, determinism is true; determinism contradicts “ought implies can”; therefore we don’t know that 'ought' implies 'can'. (2) Metaphysical Modal Argument: determinism is conceptually possible; determinism contradicts “ought implies can”; therefore “ought implies can” is not an analytic (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   37 citations