Switch to: Citations

References in:

The American Society for Aesthetics

[author unknown]
New Scholasticism 16 (3):296-296 (1942)

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. The Aesthetics of Music.Roger Scruton - 1997 - Oxford, GB: Oxford University Press.
    What is music, what is its value, and what does it mean? In this stimulating volume, Roger Scruton offers a comprehensive account of the nature and significance of music from the perspective of modern philosophy. The study begins with the metaphysics of sound. Scruton distinguishes sound from tone; analyzes rhythm, melody, and harmony; and explores the various dimensions of musical organization and musical meaning. Taking on various fashionable theories in the philosophy and theory of music, he presents a compelling case (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   94 citations  
  • Reconceptions in philosophy and other arts and sciences.Nelson Goodman - 1988 - London: Routledge. Edited by Catherine Z. Elgin.
    Knowing and Making 1. Obstacles to Knowing The theory of knowledge to be sketched here rejects both absolutism and nihilism, both unique truth and the ...
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   65 citations  
  • There are No Things That are Musical Works.Ross P. Cameron - 2008 - British Journal of Aesthetics 48 (3):295-314.
    Works of music do not appear to be concrete objects; but they do appear to be created by composers, and abstract objects do not seem to be the kind of things that can be created. In this paper I aim to develop an ontological position that lets us salvage the creativity intuition without either adopting an ontology of created abstracta or identifying musical works with concreta. I will argue that there are no musical works in our ontology, but nevertheless the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   43 citations  
  • Debates about the Ontology of Art: What are We Doing Here?Amie L. Thomasson - 2006 - Philosophy Compass 1 (3):245-255.
    Philosophy Compass, Volume 1. Oxford: Blackwell, 2006.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   39 citations  
  • The Aesthetics of Music.Gary Iseminger - 1997 - Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 57 (3):374-375.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  • Theory of Harmony.Arnold Schoenberg - 1949 - Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 7 (3):266-267.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • Music and the Emotions: The Philosophical Theories.Peter Kivy - 1986 - Philosophical Quarterly 36 (144):434-438.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  • The American Symphony Orchestra: A Social History of Musical TasteBach and Handel. The Consummation of the Baroque in MusicBaroque Book Illustration.John H. Mueller, Archibald T. Davison & Philip Hofer - 1952 - Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 11 (2):178.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Dynamic attending and responses to time.Mari Riess Jones & Marilyn Boltz - 1989 - Psychological Review 96 (3):459-491.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   51 citations  
  • A Generative Theory of Tonal Music.Fred Lerdahl & Ray Jackendoff - 1987 - Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 46 (1):94-98.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   212 citations  
  • Are There No Things That are Scientific Theories?Steven French & Peter Vickers - 2011 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 62 (4):771-804.
    The ontological status of theories themselves has recently re-emerged as a live topic in the philosophy of science. We consider whether a recent approach within the philosophy of art can shed some light on this issue. For many years philosophers of aesthetics have debated a paradox in the (meta)ontology of musical works (e.g. Levinson [1980]). Taken individually, there are good reasons to accept each of the following three propositions: (i) musical works are created; (ii) musical works are abstract objects; (iii) (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • Reconceptions in Philosophy and Other Arts and Sciences by Nelson Goodman and Catherine Z. Elgin. [REVIEW]Jonathan Adler - 1990 - Journal of Philosophy 87 (12):711-716.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • (1 other version)The value of science.Henri Poincaré - 1907 - New York,: Dover Publications. Edited by George Bruce Halsted.
    THE VALUE OF SCIENCE INTRODUCTION The search for truth should be the goal of our activities; it is the sole end worthy of them. Doubtless we should first bend our efforts to assuage human suffering, but why ? Not to suffer is a negative ...
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   91 citations  
  • Music and the Emotions: The Philosophical Theories.Malcolm Budd - 1985 - Boston: Routledge.
    It has often been claimed, and frequently denied, that music derives some or all of its artistic value from the relation in which it stands to the emotions. This book presents and subjects to critical examination the chief theories about the relationship between the art of music and the emotions.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   30 citations  
  • Rameau and Musical Thought in the Enlightenment.Thomas Christensen - 1998 - Diderot Studies 27:246-251.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • (1 other version)Music and Conceptualization.Mark Debellis - 1997 - Mind 106 (423):599-602.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • Music and Conceptualization.Mark Andrew DeBellis - 1995 - New York, NY: Cambridge University Press.
    This book is a philosophical study of the relations between hearing and thinking about music. The central problem it addresses is as follows: how is it possible to talk about what a listener perceives in terms that the listener does not recognize? By applying the concepts and techniques of analytic philosophy the author explores the ways in which musical hearing may be described as nonconceptual, and how such mental representation contrasts with conceptual thought. The author is both philosopher and musicologist (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • The Structure of Musical Revolutions.Edward Slowik - 2007 - Philosophy Now 59:9-11.
    This essay constructs a non-scientific analogy that can help to explain the nature and purpose of Kuhn's philosophical concepts, especially his notion of a scientific "paradigm". The non-scientific topic that is employed to achieve this result is the history of musical styles and the structure of musical compositions.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Music, philosophy, and cognitive science.Diana Raffman - 2011 - In Theodore Gracyk & Andrew Kania (eds.), The Routledge Companion to Philosophy and Music. New York: Routledge.
    Philosophers of music (and also music theorists) have recognized for a long time that research in the sciences, especially psychology, might have import for their own work. (Langer 1941 and Meyer 1956 are good examples.) However, while scientists had been interested in music as a subject of research (e.g., Helmholtz 1912, Seashore 1938), the discipline known as psychology of music, or more broadly cognitive science of music, came into its own only around 1980 with the publication of several landmark works. (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • (1 other version)Music and Conceptualization.Mark Debellis - 1998 - Philosophical Quarterly 48 (193):559-561.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations