Switch to: Citations

References in:

Philosophical Naturalism and Empirical Approaches to Philosophy

In Marcus Rossberg (ed.), The Cambridge Handbook of Analytic Philosophy. Cambridge University Press (forthcoming)

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. (1 other version)From Metaphysics to Ethics: A Defence of Conceptual Analysis.Frank Jackson - 1999 - Philosophical Quarterly 49 (197):539-542.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   812 citations  
  • Carnap’s Construction of the World: The Aufbau and the Emergence of Logical Empiricism.Alan W. Richardson - 1997 - Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
    This book is a major contribution to the history of analytic philosophy in general and of logical positivism in particular. It provides the first detailed and comprehensive study of Rudolf Carnap, one of the most influential figures in twentieth-century philosophy. The focus of the book is Carnap's first major work: Der logische Aufbau der Welt. It reveals tensions within the context of German epistemology and philosophy of science in the early twentieth century. Alan Richardson argues that Carnap's move to philosophy (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   70 citations  
  • Reason, Meaning and Mind.Gilbert Harman - 2000 - Philosophical Quarterly 50 (201):537-540.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Re-engineering philosophy for limited beings: piecewise approximations to reality.William C. Wimsatt - 2007 - Cambridge: Harvard University Press.
    This book offers a philosophy for error-prone humans trying to understand messy systems in the real world.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   393 citations  
  • Taking Darwin Seriously: A Naturalistic Approach to Philosophy.Michael Ruse - 1986 - New York, NY: Prometheus Books.
    Brings together traditional philosophy and modern sociobiology to examine evolutionary biology and its relation to the evolution of knowledge and ethics.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   132 citations  
  • (1 other version)The nonexistence of character traits.Gilbert Harman - 2000 - Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 100 (2):223–226.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   151 citations  
  • The hornswoggle problem.Patricia Smith Churchland - 1996 - Journal of Consciousness Studies 3 (5-6):402-8.
    Beginning with Thomas Nagel, various philosophers have propsed setting conscious experience apart from all other problems of the mind as ‘the most difficult problem’. When critically examined, the basis for this proposal reveals itself to be unconvincing and counter-productive. Use of our current ignorance as a premise to determine what we can never discover is one common logical flaw. Use of ‘I-cannot-imagine’ arguments is a related flaw. When not much is known about a domain of phenomena, our inability to imagine (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   49 citations  
  • (4 other versions)Experimental philosophy and the history of philosophy.Tom Sorell - 2018 - British Journal for the History of Philosophy 26 (5):829-849.
    Contemporary experimental philosophers sometimes use versions of an argument from the history of philosophy to defend the claim that what they do is philosophy. Although experimental philosophers conduct surveys and carry out what appear to be experiments in psychology, making them methodologically different from most analytic philosophers working today, techniques like theirs were not out of the ordinary in the philosophy of the past, early modern philosophy in particular. Or so some of them argue. This paper disputes the argument, citing (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • On Human Nature.Edward O. Wilson - 1978 - Harvard University Press.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   511 citations  
  • Kuhn’s wrong turning.Alexander Bird - 2002 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 33 (3):443-463.
    Why, despite his enormous influence in the latter part of the twentieth century, has Kuhn left no distinctively Kuhnian legacy? I argue that this is because the development of Kuhn’s own thought was in a direction opposite to that of the mainstream of the philosophy of science. In the 1970s and 1980s the philosophy of science took on board the lessons of externalism as regards reference and knowledge, and became more sympathetic to a naturalistic approach to philosophical problems. Kuhn, on (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   47 citations  
  • (1 other version)A Role for Reason in Science.Jonathan Y. Tsou - 2003 - Dialogue 42 (3):573-598.
    Michael Friedman’s Dynamics of Reason is a welcome contribution to the ongoing articulation of philosophical perspectives for understanding the sciences in the context of post-positivist philosophy of science. Two perspectives that have gained advocacy since the demise of the “received view” are Quinean naturalism and Kuhnian relativism. In his 1999 Stanford lectures, Friedman articulates and defends a neo-Kantian perspective for philosophy of science that opposes both of these perspectives. His proffered neo-Kantian perspective is presented within the context of the problem (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • The Cambridge Companion to Logical Empiricism.Alan Richardson & Thomas Uebel (eds.) - 2007 - New York: Cambridge University Press.
    If there is a movement or school that epitomizes analytic philosophy in the middle of the twentieth century, it is logical empiricism. Logical empiricists created a scientifically and technically informed philosophy of science, established mathematical logic as a topic in and tool for philosophy, and initiated the project of formal semantics. Accounts of analytic philosophy written in the middle of the twentieth century gave logical empiricism a central place in the project. The second wave of interpretative accounts was constructed to (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   28 citations  
  • The Cambridge Companion to Carnap.Michael Friedman & Richard Creath (eds.) - 2007 - Cambridge, England: Cambridge University Press.
    Rudolf Carnap is increasingly regarded as one of the most important philosophers of the twentieth century. He was one of the leading figures of the logical empiricist movement associated with the Vienna Circle and a central figure in the analytic tradition more generally. He made major contributions to philosophy of science and philosophy of logic, and, perhaps most importantly, to our understanding of the nature of philosophy as a discipline. In this volume a team of contributors explores the major themes (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   26 citations  
  • (1 other version)Key philosophers in conversation: the Cogito interviews.Andrew Pyle (ed.) - 1999 - New York: Routledge.
    This volume presents twenty of the most important interviews the journal, Cogito conducted between 1987 and 1996. Covering a wide spectrum of intellectual inquiry, from logic to metaphysics to philosophy of mind, the interviews provide an excellent introduction to philosophy in the English speaking world at the end of the century. Interviews with: Michael Dummett Peter Strawson Alasdair MacIntyre David Gauthier Nancy Cartwright Mary Warnock Hilary Putnam Daniel Dennett Bernard Williams John Cottingham Willard Quine Stephen Korner Hugh Mellor Adam Morton (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • (7 other versions)Philosophical Naturalism.Michael Friedman - 1997 - Proceedings and Addresses of the American Philosophical Association 71 (2):5 - 21.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   46 citations  
  • A Naturalistic A Priori.Georges Rey - 1998 - Philosophical Studies 92 (1/2):25 - 43.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   37 citations  
  • Knowledge and its place in nature.Hilary Kornblith - 2002 - New York: Oxford University Press.
    Hilary Kornblith argues for a naturalistic approach to investigating knowledge. Knowledge, he explains, is a feature of the natural world, and so should be investigated using scientific methods. He offers an account of knowledge derived from the science of animal behavior, and defends this against its philosophical rivals. This controversial and refreshingly original book offers philosophers a new way to do epistemology.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   233 citations  
  • The naturalists return.Philip Kitcher - 1992 - Philosophical Review 101 (1):53-114.
    This article reviews the transition between post-Fregean anti-naturalistic epistemology and contemporary naturalistic epistemologies. It traces the revival of naturalism to Quine’s critique of the "a priori", and Kuhn’s defense of historicism, and use the arguments of Quine and Kuhn to identify a position, "traditional naturalism", that combines naturalistic themes with the claim that epistemology is a normative enterprise. Pleas for more radical versions of naturalism are articulated, and briefly confronted.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   268 citations  
  • The Myth of Pain.Valerie Gray Hardcastle - 1999 - MIT Press.
    or Browse over 3500 reviews in " by Valerie Hardcastle, Ph.D. " _Metapsychology_.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   59 citations  
  • (1 other version)Reason and Morality.Alan Gewirth - 1968 - Philosophy 56 (216):266-267.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   126 citations  
  • Who Knew?: Responsiblity Without Awareness.George Sher - 2009 - New York, US: Oxford University Press USA.
    To be responsible for their acts, agents must both perform those acts voluntarily and in some sense know what they are doing. Of these requirements, the voluntariness condition has been much discussed, but the epistemic condition has received far less attention. In Who Knew? George Sher seeks to rectify that imbalance. The book is divided in two halves, the first of which criticizes a popular but inadequate way of understanding the epistemic condition, while the second seeks to develop a more (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   131 citations  
  • Sociobiology.Edward O. Wilson - 1976 - Philosophy of Science 43 (2):305-306.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   264 citations  
  • Scientific Philosophy as a Topic for History of Science.Alan Richardson - 2008 - Isis 99 (1):88-96.
    In lieu of a programmatic argument about the general relations of history of science and philosophy of science, this essay offers a particular topic in the history of philosophy of science that should be of interest to both historians and philosophers of science. It argues that questions typical of contemporary history of science could illuminate the recent history of philosophy of science and analytic philosophy. It also suggests that the history of scientific philosophy is a particularly fruitful arena for historians (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  • Taking the Naturalistic Turn, or How Real Philosophy of Science is Done.Werner Callebaut (ed.) - 1993 - Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
    Philosophers of science traditionally have ignored the details of scientific research, and the result has often been theories that lack relevance either to science or to philosophy in general. In this volume, leading philosophers of biology discuss the limitations of this tradition and the advantages of the "naturalistic turn"—the idea that the study of science is itself a scientific enterprise and should be conducted accordingly. This innovative book presents candid, informal debates among scholars who examine the benefits and problems of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   28 citations  
  • Naturalism without Fears.P. Roth - 2006 - In Stephen P. Turner & Mark W. Risjord (eds.), Handbook of Philosophy of Anthropology and Sociology. Boston: Elsevier. pp. 683--708.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • (2 other versions)Philosophy and the Mirror of Nature.Richard Rorty - 1979 - Philosophy 56 (217):427-429.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   384 citations  
  • Rebuilding the Ship while Sailing on the Water.Susan Haack - 1990 - In Barret And Gibson (ed.), Perspectives on Quine. pp. 1--1.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • Two Left Turns Make a Right: On the Curious Political Career of North American Philosophy of Science at Midcentury.Don A. Howard - 2003 - In Logical Empiricism in North America. University of Minnesota Press.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   56 citations  
  • (4 other versions)Why Reason Can’t Be Naturalized.Hilary Putnam - 1982 - Synthese 52 (1):229--47.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   87 citations  
  • By nature and by art.John Dewey - 1944 - Journal of Philosophy 41 (11):281-292.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • (1 other version)Accentuate the Negative.Joshua Alexander, Ronald Mallon & Jonathan M. Weinberg - 2013 - In Joshua Knobe & Shaun Nichols (eds.), Experimental Philosophy: Volume 2. New York, US: Oxford University Press USA.
    There are two ways of understanding experimental philosophy's process of appealing to intuitions as evidence for or against philosophical claims: the positive and negative programs. This chapter deals with how the positivist method of conceptual analysis is affected by the results of the negative program. It begins by describing direct extramentalism, semantic mentalism, conceptual mentalism, and mechanist mentalism, all of which argue that intuitions are credible sources of evidence and will therefore be shared. The negative program challenges this view by (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   37 citations  
  • (1 other version)Alvin I. Goldman, Epistemology and Cognition[REVIEW]Darryl Bruce - 1989 - Synthese 79 (1):165-169.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   383 citations  
  • Causation, Free Will, and Naturalism.Jenann Ismael - 2013 - In Don Ross, James Ladyman & Harold Kincaid (eds.), Scientific metaphysics. Oxford: Oxford University Press. pp. 208--235.
    This chapter addresses the worry that the existence of causal antecedents to your choices means that you are causally compelled to act as you do. It begins with the folk notion of cause, leads the reader through recent developments in the scientific understanding of causal concepts, and argues that those developments undermine the threat from causal antecedents. The discussion is then used as a model for a kind of naturalistic metaphysics that takes its lead from science, letting everyday concepts be (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  • Quine's behaviorism cum empiricism.Roger F. Gibson - 2004 - In The Cambridge companion to Quine. New York: Cambridge University Press. pp. 181--199.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  • (1 other version)Dewey on naturalism, realism and science.Peter Godfrey-Smith - 2002 - Proceedings of the Philosophy of Science Association 2002 (3):S25-S35.
    An interpretation of John Dewey’s views about realism, science, and naturalistic philosophy is presented. Dewey should be seen as an unorthodox realist, with respect to both general metaphysical debates about realism and with respect to debates about the aims and achievements of science.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  • Kornblith on Knowledge and Epistemology.Laurence Bonjour - 2006 - Philosophical Studies 127 (2):317-335.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • The epistemology of science after Quine.Paul A. Roth - 2005 - In Martin Curd & Stathis Psillos (eds.), The Routledge Companion to Philosophy of Science. New York: Routledge. pp. 3.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations