Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. (1 other version)The meaning of 'meaning'.Hilary Putnam - 1975 - Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science 7:131-193.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1429 citations  
  • (1 other version)Identity and necessity.Saul A. Kripke - 1971 - In Milton Karl Munitz (ed.), Identity and individuation. New York,: New York University Press. pp. 135-164.
    are synthetic a priori judgements possible?" In both cases, i~thas usually been t'aken for granted in fife one case by Kant that synthetic a priori judgements were possible, and in the other case in contemporary,'d-". philosophical literature that contingent statements of identity are ppss. ible. I do not intend to deal with the Kantian question except to mention:ssj~".
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   435 citations  
  • From Metaphysics to Ethics: A Defence of Conceptual Analysis.Frank Jackson - 1998 - New York: Oxford University Press.
    Frank Jackson champions the cause of conceptual analysis as central to philosophical inquiry. In recent years conceptual analysis has been undervalued and widely misunderstood, suggests Jackson. He argues that such analysis is mistakenly clouded in mystery, preventing a whole range of important questions from being productively addressed. He anchors his argument in discussions of specific philosophical issues, starting with the metaphysical doctrine of physicalism and moving on, via free will, meaning, personal identity, motion, and change, to ethics and the philosophy (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1065 citations  
  • (1 other version)The Empirical Stance.Bas C. Van Fraassen - 2002 - New York: Yale University Press.
    What is empiricism and what could it be? Bas . van Fraassen, one of the world’s foremost contributors to philosophical logic and the philosophy of science, here undertakes a fresh consideration of these questions and offers a program for renewal of the empiricist tradition. The empiricist tradition is not and could not be defined by common doctrines, but embodies a certain stance in philosophy, van Fraassen says. This stance is displayed first of all in a searing, recurrent critique of metaphysics, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   265 citations  
  • The Dappled World: A Study of the Boundaries of Science.Nancy Cartwright - 1999 - New York, NY: Cambridge University Press.
    It is often supposed that the spectacular successes of our modern mathematical sciences support a lofty vision of a world completely ordered by one single elegant theory. In this book Nancy Cartwright argues to the contrary. When we draw our image of the world from the way modern science works - as empiricism teaches us we should - we end up with a world where some features are precisely ordered, others are given to rough regularity and still others behave in (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   571 citations  
  • Reason, Truth and History.Hilary Putnam - 1981 - New York: Cambridge University Press.
    Hilary Putnam deals in this book with some of the most fundamental persistent problems in philosophy: the nature of truth, knowledge and rationality. His aim is to break down the fixed categories of thought which have always appeared to define and constrain the permissible solutions to these problems.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   601 citations  
  • Is Water Necessarily H2O.Hilary Putnam - 1983 - In ¸ Iteputnam:Rhfbook. pp. 54--79.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   214 citations  
  • What Water Is or Back to Thales.Avrum Stroll - 1989 - Midwest Studies in Philosophy 14 (1):258-274.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Explanatory unification and the causal structure of the world.Philip Kitcher - 1962 - In Philip Kitcher & Wesley C. Salmon (eds.), Scientific Explanation. Univ of Minnesota Pr. pp. 410-505.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   518 citations  
  • Rigidity and kind.Joseph LaPorte - 2000 - Philosophical Studies 97 (3):293-316.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   58 citations  
  • Negative, infinite, and hotter than infinite temperatures.Philip Ehrlich - 1982 - Synthese 50 (2):233 - 277.
    We examine the notions of negative, infinite and hotter than infinite temperatures and show how these unusual concepts gain legitimacy in quantum statistical mechanics. We ask if the existence of an infinite temperature implies the existence of an actual infinity and argue that it does not. Since one can sensibly talk about hotter than infinite temperatures, we ask if one could legitimately speak of other physical quantities, such as length and duration, in analogous terms. That is, could there be longer (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   34 citations  
  • The discovery that water is H2O.Paul Needham - 2002 - International Studies in the Philosophy of Science 16 (3):205 – 226.
    What are the criteria determining the individuation of chemical kinds? Recent philosophical discussion, which puts too much emphasis on microstructure, seems to presuppose a reductionist conception not motivated by the scientific facts. The present article traces the development of the traditional notion of a substance with the rise of modern chemistry from the end of the 18th century with a view to correcting this speculative distortion.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   52 citations  
  • (3 other versions)What the externalist can know A Priori.Paul A. Boghossian - 1997 - Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 97 (2):161-75.
    Compatibilism combines an externalist view of mental content with a doctrine of privileged self‐knowledge. The essay presents a reductio of compatibilism by arguing that if compatibilism were true, we would be in a position to know certain facts about the world a priori, facts that no one can reasonably believe are knowable a priori. Whether this should be taken to cast doubt on externalism or privileged self‐knowledge is not discussed. Consideration is given to the ’empty case’—the case in which a (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   77 citations  
  • Putnam's theory on the reference of substance terms.Eddy M. Zemach - 1976 - Journal of Philosophy 73 (March):116-27.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   45 citations  
  • New Essays on Human Understanding.G. W. Leibniz - 1981 - Tijdschrift Voor Filosofie 45 (3):489-490.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   178 citations  
  • Whither physical objects?Willard Quine - 1976 - In R. S. Cohen, P. K. Feyerabend & M. Wartofsky (eds.), Essays in Memory of Imre Lakatos. Reidel. pp. 497--504.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   61 citations  
  • Water is not H 2 O.B. C. Malt - 1994 - Cognitive Psychology 27:41--70.
    What makes a liquid water? A strong version of ``psychological essentialis'' predicts that people use the presence or absence of H2O as the primary determinant of what liquids they call ``water.'' To test this prediction, subjects were asked to judge the amount of H2O in liquids called ``water'' and liquids not called ``water.'' Neither their beliefs about the simple presence/absence of H2O nor about the proportion of H2O in the liquids accounted well for which ones are normally called "water." Typicality (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   56 citations  
  • Chemical kind term reference and the discovery of essence.Joe LaPorte - 1996 - Noûs 30 (1):112-132.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   42 citations  
  • Necessarily, salt dissolves in water.Alexander Bird - 2001 - Analysis 61 (4):267-274.
    In this paper I aim to show that a certain law of nature, namely that common salt (sodium chloride) dissolves in water, is metaphysically necessary. The importance of this result is that it conflicts with a widely shared intuition that the laws of nature (most if not all) are contingent. There have been debates over whether some laws, such as Newton’s second law, might be definitional of their key terms and hence necessary. But the law that salt dissolves in water (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   45 citations  
  • Realism and reason.Hilary Putnam (ed.) - 1983 - New York: Cambridge University Press.
    This is the third volume of Hilary Putnam's philosophical papers, published in paperback for the first time. The volume contains his major essays from 1975 to 1982, which reveal a large shift in emphasis in the 'realist'_position developed in his earlier work. While not renouncing those views, Professor Putnam has continued to explore their epistemological consequences and conceptual history. He now, crucially, sees theories of truth and of meaning that derive from a firm notion of reference as inadequate.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   284 citations  
  • Aristotelian essentialism revisited.Charlotte Witt - 1989 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 27 (2):285-298.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • (1 other version)Meanings just ain't in the head.Michael Devitt - 1990 - In George Boolos (ed.), Meaning and Method: Essays in Honor of Hilary Putnam. Cambridge and New York: Cambridge University Press. pp. 79--104.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   23 citations  
  • Observation and the Hidden.Avrum Stroll - 1991 - Dialectica 45 (2‐3):165-179.
    SummaryA new form of expiricism has developed recently which drives a wedge between the principles that science alone will provide a true account of reality and that any such account must be grounded in observation. These empiricists hold firm to the first principle, but have qualified adherence to the second. Using arguments like Putnam's Twin Earth scenario, they contend that a search for reality must go beneath the observable to find the microstructure of substances . Their arguments are fallacious and (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • The Natural Shiftiness of Natural Kinds.Ronald de Sousa - 1984 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 14 (4):561-580.
    The Philosophical search for Natural Kinds is motivated by the hope of finding ontological categories that are independent of our interests. Other requirements, of varying importance, are commonly made of kinds that claim to be natural. But no such categories are to be found. Virtually any kind can be termed ‘natural’ relative to some set of interests and epistemic priorities. Science determines those priorities at any particular stage of its progress, and what kinds are most ‘natural’ in that sense is (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • Natural kinds.D. H. Mellor - 1977 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 28 (4):299-312.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   77 citations  
  • Natural kind terms and recognitional capacities.Jessica Brown - 1998 - Mind 107 (426):275-303.
    The main contribution of this paper is a new account of how a community may introduce a term for a natural kind in advance of knowing the correct scientific account of that kind. The account is motivated by the inadequacy of the currently dominant accounts of how a community may do this, namely those proposed by Kripke and by Putman. Their accounts fail to deal satisfactorily with the facts that (1) typically, an item that instantiates one natural kind instantiates several (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   37 citations  
  • Individualism and Social Science.Rajeev BHARGAVA - 1992 - Revue Philosophique de la France Et de l'Etranger 185 (3):393-394.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  • Meaning, prototypes and the future of cognitive science.Jaap van Brakel - 1991 - Minds and Machines 1 (3):233-57.
    In this paper I evaluate the soundness of the prototype paradigm, in particular its basic assumption that there are pan-human psychological essences or core meanings that refer to basic-level natural kinds, explaining why, on the whole, human communication and learning are successful. Instead I argue that there are no particular pan-human basic elements for thought, meaning and cognition, neither prototypes, nor otherwise. To illuminate my view I draw on examples from anthropology. More generally I argue that the prototype paradigm exemplifies (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Representation and Reality.H. Putnam - 1988 - Tijdschrift Voor Filosofie 52 (1):168-168.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   272 citations  
  • Correspondence and Reduction in Chemistry.Eric R. Scerri - 1993 - In S. French & H. Kamminga (eds.), Correspondence, Invariance and Heuristics: Essays in Honour of Heinz Post. Dordrecht: Reidel. pp. 45--64.
    The article discusses some of Heinz Post's views on correspondence and whether revolutions occur in science a la Kuhn. For example Post points out that the periodic table of the chemical elements has withstood any revolutions. Specific issues examined include the Paneth-Fajans controversy, the extent to which quantum mechanics provides an explanation for the periodic table and ab initio calculations in quantum chemistry.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • Polywater and experimental realism.J. Van Brakel - 1993 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 44 (4):775-784.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • A note on the nature of "water".Barbara Abbott - 1997 - Mind 106 (422):311-319.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   23 citations  
  • Science and essence.Quassim Cassam - 1986 - Philosophy 61 (235):95--107.
    The terminology of ‘essence’ and ‘accident’, which it is customary to trace back to Aristotle, has been given a new lease of life by recent writing on logic and metaphysics. Aristotle's notion of ‘essence’ is notoriously difficult and obscure, but the works of Putnam 1 on natural kinds, Kripke 2 on naming and Wiggins 3 on identity may be seen as providing a new rationale, with a distinctive scientific twist, for talk of essences. This revival in the fortunes of essentialism (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Is natural kindness a natural kind?D. Gene Witmer & John Sarnecki - 1998 - Philosophical Studies 90 (3):245-264.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Meaning Holism.Hilary Putnam - 1983 - In ¸ Iteputnam:Rhfbook. pp. 278--302.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   26 citations  
  • Is Putnam inconsistent and parochial?James Beattie - 1993 - Australasian Journal of Philosophy 71 (3):316 – 324.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Higher and Lower Essential Natures.Crawford L. Elder - 1994 - American Philosophical Quarterly 31 (3):255 - 265.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Reduction and abduction in chemistry‐a response to Scerri.Paul Needham - 1999 - International Studies in the Philosophy of Science 13 (2):169 – 184.
    Eric Scerri has proposed an account of how reduction might be understood in chemistry. He claims to build on a general aspect of Popper's views which survives his otherwise heavy criticism, namely adherence to actual scientific practice. This is contrasted with Nagel's conception, which Scerri takes to be the philosopher's standard notion. I argue that his proposal, interesting though it is, is not so foreign to ideas in the tradition within which Nagel wrote as Scerri would have us believe. Moreover, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Scientific Realism and Ordinary Usage.Oswald Hanfling - 1984 - Philosophical Investigations 7 (3):187-205.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Metaphysical necessity and epistemic location.Robert Farrell - 1983 - Australasian Journal of Philosophy 61 (3):283 – 294.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Essence and scientific discovery in Kripke and Putnam.Edward Averill - 1982 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 43 (2):253-257.
    THE CLAIM THAT IF GOLD HAS THE ATOMIC NUMBER 79 THEN GOLD NECESSARILY HAS THE ATOMIC NUMBER 79 IS SHOWN TO BE FALSE. THE KRIPKE-PUTNAM ARGUMENT FOR THIS CLAIM IS REWORKED TO SHOW THIS: IF A PROPERTY OF GOLD (LIKE ATOMIC NUMBER) PLAYS A BASIC ROLE IN A THEORY OF SUBSTANCE, THAT IS BOTH TRUE AND THE BEST MOST COMPREHENSIVE THEORY OF SUBSTANCE POSSIBLE, THEN GOLD NECESSARILY HAS THIS PROPERTY. 'BASIC ROLE' IS EXPLAINED.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations