Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. Origins of Mendelism.Robert Cecil Olby - 1985 - Journal of the History of Biology 20 (1):132-133.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   38 citations  
  • Genetics and Reductionism.Sahotra Sarkar - 2012 - Cambridge University Press.
    With the advent of the Human Genome Project there have been many claims for the genetic origins of complex human behavior including insanity, criminality, and intelligence. But what does it really mean to call something 'genetic'? This is the fundamental question that Sahotra Sarkar's book addresses. The author analyses the nature of reductionism in classical and molecular genetics. He shows that there are two radically different kinds of reductionist explanation: genetic reduction (as found in classical genetics) and physical reduction (found (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   95 citations  
  • Interfield theories.Lindley Darden & Nancy Maull - 1977 - Philosophy of Science 44 (1):43-64.
    This paper analyzes the generation and function of hitherto ignored or misrepresented interfield theories , theories which bridge two fields of science. Interfield theories are likely to be generated when two fields share an interest in explaining different aspects of the same phenomenon and when background knowledge already exists relating the two fields. The interfield theory functions to provide a solution to a characteristic type of theoretical problem: how are the relations between fields to be explained? In solving this problem (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   266 citations  
  • Conceptual change, cross-theoretical explanation, and the unity of science.Richard M. Burian - 1975 - Synthese 32 (1-2):1 - 28.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Opposition to the Mendelian-chromosome theory: The physiological and developmental genetics of Richard Goldschmidt.Garland E. Allen - 1974 - Journal of the History of Biology 7 (1):49-92.
    We may now ask the question: In what historical perspective should we place the work of Richard Goldschmidt? There is no doubt that in the period 1910–1950 Goldschmidt was an important and prolific figure in the history of biology in general, and of genetics in particular. His textbook on physiological genetics, published in 1938, was an amazing compendium of ideas put forward in the previous half-century about how genes influence physiology and development. His earlier studies on the genetic and geographic (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  • Versions.[author unknown] - 1904 - The Classical Review 18 (1):69-70.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   22 citations  
  • Versions.[author unknown] - 1909 - The Classical Review 23 (4):138-139.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  • Versions.[author unknown] - 1908 - The Classical Review 22 (3):101-101.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   21 citations  
  • The Structure of Science: Problems in the Logic of Scientific Explanation.Ernest Nagel - 1961 - New York, NY, USA: Harcourt, Brace & World.
    Introduction: Science and Common Sense Long before the beginnings of modern civilization, men ac- quired vast funds of information about their environment. ...
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   483 citations  
  • The Structure of Scientific Revolutions.Thomas Samuel Kuhn - 1962 - Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Edited by Otto Neurath.
    A scientific community cannot practice its trade without some set of received beliefs. These beliefs form the foundation of the "educational initiation that prepares and licenses the student for professional practice". The nature of the "rigorous and rigid" preparation helps ensure that the received beliefs are firmly fixed in the student's mind. Scientists take great pains to defend the assumption that scientists know what the world is like...To this end, "normal science" will often suppress novelties which undermine its foundations. Research (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2705 citations  
  • Why the Anti-reductionist Consensus Won’t Survive the Case of Classical Mendelian Genetics.C. Kenneth Waters - 1990 - PSA Proceedings of the Biennial Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association 1990 (1):125-139.
    Philosophers now treat the relationship between Classical Mendelian Genetics and molecular biology as a paradigm of nonreduction and this example is playing an increasingly prominent role in debates about the reducibility of theories ranging from macrosocial science to folk psychology. Patricia Churchland (1986), for example, draws an analogy between the alleged elimination of the “causal mainstay” of classical genetics and her view that today’s psychological theory will be eliminated by neuroscience. Patricia Kitcher takes an autonomous rather than eliminativist view of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • What was classical genetics?C. Kenneth Waters - 2004 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 35 (4):783-809.
    I present an account of classical genetics to challenge theory-biased approaches in the philosophy of science. Philosophers typically assume that scientific knowledge is ultimately structured by explanatory reasoning and that research programs in well-established sciences are organized around efforts to fill out a central theory and extend its explanatory range. In the case of classical genetics, philosophers assume that the knowledge was structured by T. H. Morgan’s theory of transmission and that research throughout the later 1920s, 30s, and 40s was (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   60 citations  
  • Heroic antireductionism and genetics: A tale of one science.Russell E. Vance - 1996 - Philosophy of Science 63 (3):45.
    In this paper I provide a novel argument against the claim that classical genetics is being reduced to molecular genetics. Specifically, I demonstrate that reductionists must subscribe to the unargued and problematic thesis that molecular genetics is 'independent' of classical genetics. I also argue that several standard antireductionist positions can be faulted for unnecessarily conceding the Independence Thesis to the reductionists. In place of a 'tale of two sciences', I offer a 'heroic' stance that denies classical genetics is being reduced, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  • The Watson-Crick model and reductionism.Kenneth F. Schaffner - 1969 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 20 (4):325-348.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   90 citations  
  • The Structure of Biological Science by Alexander Rosenberg. [REVIEW]Robert N. Brandon - 1987 - Journal of Philosophy 84 (4):224-227.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   35 citations  
  • The Structure of Science.Ernest Nagel - 1961 - Les Etudes Philosophiques 17 (2):275-275.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   874 citations  
  • From presentation to representation in E. B. Wilson's the cell.Jane Maienschein - 1991 - Biology and Philosophy 6 (2):227-254.
    Diagrams make it possible to present scientific facts in more abstract and generalized form. While some detail is lost, simplified and accessible knowledge is gained. E. B. Wilson's work in cytology provides a case study of changing uses of diagrams and accompanying abstraction. In his early work, Wilson presented his data in photographs, which he saw as coming closest to “fact.” As he gained confidence in his interpretations, and as he sought to provide a generalized textbook account of cell development, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • The externalized retina: Selection and mathematization in the visual documentation of objects in the life sciences. [REVIEW]Michael Lynch - 1988 - Human Studies 11 (2-3):201 - 234.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   67 citations  
  • 1953 and all that. A tale of two sciences.Philip Kitcher - 1984 - Philosophical Review 93 (3):335-373.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   264 citations  
  • Extending Ourselves: Computational Science, Empiricism, and Scientific Method.Paul Humphreys - 2004 - New York, US: Oxford University Press.
    Computational methods such as computer simulations, Monte Carlo methods, and agent-based modeling have become the dominant techniques in many areas of science. Extending Ourselves contains the first systematic philosophical account of these new methods, and how they require a different approach to scientific method. Paul Humphreys draws a parallel between the ways in which such computational methods have enhanced our abilities to mathematically model the world, and the more familiar ways in which scientific instruments have expanded our access to the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   279 citations  
  • Reduction in Genetics—Biology or Philosophy?David L. Hull - 1972 - Philosophy of Science 39 (4):491-499.
    A belief common among philosophers and biologists alike is that Mendelian genetics has been or is in the process of being reduced to molecular genetics, in the sense of formal theory reduction current in the literature. The purpose of this paper is to show that there are numerous empirical and conceptual difficulties which stand in the way of establishing a systematic inferential relation between Mendelian and molecular genetics. These difficulties, however, have little to do with the traditional objections which have (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   54 citations  
  • Reduction in genetics.David L. Hull - 1979 - Philosophy of Science 46 (2):316-320.
    In a recent paper, William K. Goosens objects to the arguments I set out some time ago attacking the logical empiricist analysis of reduction as applied to genetics. In these works I did not argue against the claim that Mendelian genetics was being reduced to molecular biology. Nor did I conclude, as Goosens asserts, that in the case of genetics, “reduction is insignificant”. To the contrary, I repeatedly stated that, “given our pre-analytic intuitions about reduction,” the reduction of Mendelian to (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • The Structure of Biological Science.Alexander Rosenberg - 1985 - New York: Cambridge University Press.
    This book provides a comprehensive guide to the conceptual methodological, and epistemological problems of biology, and treats in depth the major developments in molecular biology and evolutionary theory that have transformed both biology and its philosophy in recent decades. At the same time the work is a sustained argument for a particular philosophy of biology that unifies disparate issues and offers a framework for expectations about the future directions of the life sciences. The argument explores differences between autonomist and anti-autonomist (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   263 citations  
  • Formats of representation in scientific theorizing.Marion Vorms - 2009 - In Paul Humphreys & Cyrille Imbert (eds.), Models, Simulations, and Representations. Routledge. pp. 250-273.
    This paper is intended to sketch the definition of a methodological tool -- the notion of a format of representation -- for the study of scientific theorising. One of its main assumption is that a philosophical study of theorising needs to pay attention to other types of units of analysis than the traditional ones, namely, theories and models approached in a logical and structural way, since scientific reasoning is always led on concrete representational devices and depends upon their specific properties. (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  • The theoretician's gambits: scientific representations, their formats and content.Marion Vorms - 2010 - In Lorenzo Magnani, Walter Carnielli & Claudio Pizzi (eds.), Model-Based Reasoning in Science and Technology. Springer. pp. 533--558.
    It is quite widely acknowledged, in the field of cognitive science, that the format in which a set of data is displayed (lists, graphs, arrays, etc.) matters to the agents' performances in achieving various cognitive tasks, such as problem-solving or decision-making. This paper intends to show that formats also matter in the case of theoretical representations, namely general representations expressing hypotheses, and not only in the case of data displays. Indeed, scientists have limited cognitive abilities, and representations in different formats (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Informal Aspects of Theory Reduction.David L. Hull - 1974 - PSA: Proceedings of the Biennial Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association 1974:653 - 670.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   32 citations  
  • The Structure of Science: Problems in the Logic of Scientific Explanation.Ernest Nagel - 1961 - Mind 72 (287):429-441.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   287 citations  
  • Formal and material theories in philosophy of science: a methodological interpretation.Alan Love - 2012 - In Henk W. de Regt (ed.), Epsa Philosophy of Science: Amsterdam 2009. Dordrecht: Springer. pp. 175--185.
    John Norton’s argument that all formal theories of induction fail raises substantive questions about the philosophical analysis of scientific reasoning. What are the criteria of adequacy for philosophical theories of induction, explanation, or theory structure? Is more than one adequate theory possible? Using a generalized version of Norton’s argument, I demonstrate that the competition between formal and material theories in philosophy of science results from adhering to different criteria of adequacy. This situation encourages an interpretation of “formal” and “material” as (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Consciousness and the Brain: A Scientific and Philosophical Inquiry.G. G. Globus, G. Maxwell & I. Savodnik - 1978 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 29 (1):61-68.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   48 citations  
  • The Structure of Science: Problems in the Logic of Scientific Explanation.Ernest Nagel - 1962 - Philosophy 37 (142):372-374.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   218 citations  
  • The Structure of Biological Science.Alexander Rosenberg - 1987 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 38 (1):119-121.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   186 citations  
  • The Structure of Biological Science.Alexander Rosenberg - 1986 - Journal of the History of Biology 19 (1):161-162.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   128 citations  
  • Origins of Mendelism.R. C. Olby & W. B. Provine - 1973 - Journal of the History of Biology 6 (1):125-154.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   37 citations  
  • Genetics and Reductionism.Sahotra Sarkar - 2000 - Philosophical Quarterly 50 (198):128-130.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   100 citations  
  • Lords of the Fly: Drosophila Genetics and the Experimental Life.Robert E. Kohler - 1995 - Journal of the History of Biology 28 (1):167-170.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   168 citations  
  • Why the antireductionist consensus won't survive the case of classical Mendelian genetics.C. Kenneth Waters - 1990 - Philosophy of Science Association 1:125-39.
    Philosophers now treat the relationship between classical genetics and molecular biology as a paradigm of nonreduction and this example is playing an increasingly prominent role in debates about the reducibility of theories in other sciences. This paper shows that the anti-reductionist consensus about genetics will not withstand serious scrutiny. In addition to defusing the main anti-reductionist objections, this critical analysis uncovers tell-tale signs of a significant reduction in progress. It also identifies philosophical issues relevant to gaining a better understanding of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   25 citations  
  • Reductionism, levels of organization, and the mind-body problem.William C. Wimsatt - 1976 - In Gordon G. Globus (ed.), Consciousness and the Brain. Plenum Press.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   122 citations