Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. On the Pragmatics of Social Interaction: Preliminary Studies in the Theory of Communicative Action.Jürgen Habermas - 2002 - MIT Press.
    Habermas's 1971 Gauss Lectures, plus two additional essays, outlining an intersubjective approach to social theory.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   22 citations  
  • Committees and consensus: How many heads are better than one?Peter Caws - 1991 - Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 16 (4):375-391.
    The first section of this paper asks why the notion of consensus has recently come to the fore in the medical humanities, and suggests that the answer is a function of growing technological and professional complexity. The next two sections examine the concept of consensus analytically, citing some of the recent philosophical literature. The fourth section looks at committee deliberations and their desirable outcomes, and questions the degree to which consensus serves those outcomes. In the fifth and last section it (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • The Fate of Knowledge.Helen E. Longino - 2001 - Princeton University Press.
    Helen Longino seeks to break the current deadlock in the ongoing wars between philosophers of science and sociologists of science--academic battles founded on disagreement about the role of social forces in constructing scientific knowledge. While many philosophers of science downplay social forces, claiming that scientific knowledge is best considered as a product of cognitive processes, sociologists tend to argue that numerous noncognitive factors influence what scientists learn, how they package it, and how readily it is accepted. Underlying this disagreement, however, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   332 citations  
  • Dialogic Consensus in Medicine—A Justification Claim.Paul Walker & Terence Lovat - 2019 - Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 44 (1):71-84.
    The historical emphasis of medical ethics, based on substantive frameworks and principles derived from them, is no longer seen as sufficiently sensitive to the moral pluralism characteristic of our current era. We argue that moral decision-making in clinical situations is more properly derived from a process of dialogic consensus. This process entails an inclusive, noncoercive, and self-reflective dialogue within the community affected. In order to justify this approach, we make two claims—the first epistemic, and the second normative. The epistemic claim (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Compromise, pluralism, and deliberation.Daniel Weinstock - 2017 - Critical Review of International Social and Political Philosophy 20 (5):636-655.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Justification and Application: Remarks on Discourse Ethics.Jürgen Habermas - 1993 - Polity.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   120 citations  
  • Possibilities of consensus: Toward democratic moral discourse.Bruce Jennings - 1991 - Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 16 (4):447-463.
    The concept of consensus is often appealed to in discussions of biomedical ethics and applied ethics, and it plays an important role in many influential ethical theories. Consensus is an especially influential notion among theorists who reject ethical realism and who frame ethics as a practice of discourse rather than a body of objective knowledge. It is also a practically important notion when moral decision making is subject to bureaucratic organization and oversight, as is increasingly becoming the case in medicine. (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  • On the possibility of principled moral compromise.Daniel Weinstock - 2013 - Critical Review of International Social and Political Philosophy 16 (4):537-556.
    Simon May has argued that the notion of a principled compromise is incoherent. Reasons to compromise are always in his view strategic: though we think that the position we defend is still the right one, we compromise on this view in order to avoid the undesirable consequences that might flow from not compromising. I argue against May that there are indeed often principled reasons to compromise, and that these reasons are in fact multiple. First, compromises evince respect for persons that (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   34 citations  
  • In Defence of Moral Pluralism and Compromise in Health Care Networks.Kasper Raus, Eric Mortier & Kristof Eeckloo - 2018 - Health Care Analysis 26 (4):362-379.
    The organisation of health care is rapidly changing. There is a trend to move away from individual health care institutions towards transmural integrated care and interorganizational collaboration in networks. However, within such collaboration and network there is often likely to be a pluralism of values as different health care institutions often have very different values. For this paper, we examine three different models of how we believe institutions can come to collaborate in networks, and thus reap the potential benefits of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Critical Reflections on Conventional Concepts and Beliefs in Bioethics.J. Clint Parker - 2019 - Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 44 (1):1-9.
    An important role of the philosopher is to critically reflect on what is often taken for granted, using the tools of argument and analysis. This article engages with six different papers that offer critical reflections on conventional concepts and beliefs in bioethics regarding informed consent, continuous deep sedation, traditional moral theories underlying bioethical thinking, the definition of mental disease, and codes of ethics for particular medical specialties.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • (1 other version)Knowledge and Human Interests.Jurgen Habermas - 1981 - Ethics 91 (2):280-295.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   243 citations  
  • Rational consensual procedure: Argumentation or weighted averaging?Jane Braaten - 1987 - Synthese 71 (3):347 - 354.
    The following is a defense of Jurgen Habermas' argumentational consensual procedure against Keith Lehrer and Carl Wagner's weighted averaging consensual procedure (and, I tentatively claim, against any weighted averaging consensual procedure). The argument is twofold: if Lehrer and Wagner intend, implicity, to replace what is for Habermas the metatheoretical stage of a discussion with the aggregation of judgments of respect, then their procedure fails to make use of all available information and the participants are not committed to the weighted average (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • (1 other version)Knowledge and Human Interests.Jürgen Habermas & Jeremy Shapiro - 1973 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 2 (4):545-569.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   154 citations  
  • Dialogic Consensus In Clinical Decision-Making.Paul Walker & Terry Lovat - 2016 - Journal of Bioethical Inquiry 13 (4):571-580.
    This paper is predicated on the understanding that clinical encounters between clinicians and patients should be seen primarily as inter-relations among persons and, as such, are necessarily moral encounters. It aims to relocate the discussion to be had in challenging medical decision-making situations, including, for example, as the end of life comes into view, onto a more robust moral philosophical footing than is currently commonplace. In our contemporary era, those making moral decisions must be cognizant of the existence of perspectives (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • The independence of medical ethics.Johan Brännmark - 2019 - Medicine, Health Care and Philosophy 22 (1):5-15.
    This paper discusses the relation between medical ethics and general moral theory, the argument being that medical ethics is best seen as independent from general moral theory. According to this independence thesis, here explicated in terms of what is called a disunitarian stance, the very idea of applied ethics, which is often seen as underlying medical ethics (as well as many other more specific fields of ethics), is misguided. We should instead think of medical ethics as a domain-specific ethical inquiry (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Bioethics: why philosophy is essential for progress.Julian Savulescu - 2015 - Journal of Medical Ethics 41 (1):28-33.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   30 citations  
  • Reconciling Global Duties with Special Responsibilities: Towards a Dialogical Ethics.An Verlinden - 2010 - In Stan van Hooft & Wim Vandekerckhove (eds.), Questioning Cosmopolitanism. Springer. pp. 83--103.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • (1 other version)The Concept of Moral Consensus: The Case of Technological Interventions into Human Reproduction.Kurt Bayertz & Udo Schuklenk - 1997 - Bioethics 11 (5):453-454.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Culturally Competent Bioethics: Analysis of a Case Study.Ben Gray - 2015 - Journal of Bioethical Inquiry 12 (2):361-367.
    This paper discusses the Saudi Arabian case by Abdallah Adlan and Henk ten Have, published in a 2012 issue of the Journal of Bioethical Inquiry, regarding a congenitally disabled child enrolled in a research project examining the genetics of her condition. During the course of the study, her father was found not to be genetically related, and the case discussed the dilemma between disclosing to the family all findings as promised in consent documents or withholding paternity information because of the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations