Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. Completeness of an ancient logic.John Corcoran - 1972 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 37 (4):696-702.
    In previous articles, it has been shown that the deductive system developed by Aristotle in his "second logic" is a natural deduction system and not an axiomatic system as previously had been thought. It was also stated that Aristotle's logic is self-sufficient in two senses: First, that it presupposed no other logical concepts, not even those of propositional logic; second, that it is (strongly) complete in the sense that every valid argument expressible in the language of the system is deducible (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   79 citations  
  • A Mathematical Model of Aristotle’s Syllogistic.John Corcoran - 1973 - Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie 55 (2):191-219.
    In the present article we attempt to show that Aristotle's syllogistic is an underlying logiC which includes a natural deductive system and that it isn't an axiomatic theory as had previously been thought. We construct a mathematical model which reflects certain structural aspects of Aristotle's logic. We examine the relation of the model to the system of logic envisaged in scattered parts of Prior and Posterior Analytics. Our interpretation restores Aristotle's reputation as a logician of consummate imagination and skill. Several (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   23 citations  
  • The gentzenization and decidability of RW.Ross T. Brady - 1990 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 19 (1):35 - 73.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   21 citations  
  • The Development of Modus Ponens in Antiquity: From Aristotle to the 2nd Century AD.Susanne Bobzien - 2002 - Phronesis 47 (4):359-394.
    ABSTRACT: This paper traces the earliest development of the most basic principle of deduction, i.e. modus ponens (or Law of Detachment). ‘Aristotelian logic’, as it was taught from late antiquity until the 20th century, commonly included a short presentation of the argument forms modus (ponendo) ponens, modus (tollendo) tollens, modus ponendo tollens, and modus tollendo ponens. In late antiquity, arguments of these forms were generally classified as ‘hypothetical syllogisms’. However, Aristotle did not discuss such arguments, nor did he call any (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • Aristotle's Modal Syllogistic.Marko Malink - 2013 - Cambridge, MA and London: Harvard University Press.
    Aristotle was the founder not only of logic but also of modal logic. In the Prior Analytics he developed a complex system of modal syllogistic which, while influential, has been disputed since antiquity--and is today widely regarded as incoherent. Combining analytic rigor with keen sensitivity to historical context, Marko Malink makes clear that the modal syllogistic forms a consistent, integrated system of logic, one that is closely related to other areas of Aristotle's philosophy. Aristotle's modal syllogistic differs significantly from modern (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   53 citations  
  • Semantics for Pure Theories of Connexive Implication.Yale Weiss - 2022 - Review of Symbolic Logic 15 (3):591-606.
    In this article, I provide Urquhart-style semilattice semantics for three connexive logics in an implication-negation language (I call these “pure theories of connexive implication”). The systems semantically characterized include the implication-negation fragment of a connexive logic of Wansing, a relevant connexive logic recently developed proof-theoretically by Francez, and an intermediate system that is novel to this article. Simple proofs of soundness and completeness are given and the semantics is used to establish various facts about the systems (e.g., that two of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Negation as Cancellation, Connexive Logic, and qLPm.Heinrich Wansing - 2018 - Australasian Journal of Logic 15 (2):476-488.
    In this paper, we shall consider the so-called cancellation view of negation and the inferential role of contradictions. We will discuss some of the problematic aspects of negation as cancellation, such as its original presentation by Richard and Valery Routley and its role in motivating connexive logic. Furthermore, we will show that the idea of inferential ineffectiveness of contradictions can be conceptually separated from the cancellation model of negation by developing a system we call qLPm, a combination of Graham Priest’s (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  • What is a syllogism?Timothy J. Smiley - 1973 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 2 (1):136 - 154.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   113 citations  
  • On systems containing Aristotle's thesis.R. Routley & H. Montgomery - 1968 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 33 (1):82-96.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  • Premise order in Aristotle's syllogistic.Lynn E. Rose - 1966 - Phronesis 11 (2):154-158.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Negation as cancellation, and connexive logic.Graham Priest - 1999 - Topoi 18 (2):141-148.
    Of the various accounts of negation that have been offered by logicians in the history of Western logic, that of negation as cancellation is a very distinctive one, quite different from the explosive accounts of modern "classical" and intuitionist logics, and from the accounts offered in standard relevant and paraconsistent logics. Despite its ancient origin, however, a precise understanding of the notion is still wanting. The first half of this paper offers one. Both conceptually and historically, the account of negation (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   49 citations  
  • Aristotle and syllogisms from false premisses.G. Patzig - 1959 - Mind 68 (270):186-192.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Connexive implication.Storrs Mccall - 1966 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 31 (3):415-433.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   68 citations  
  • The Logic of Negation in Boethius.Christopher Martin - 1991 - Phronesis 36 (3):277-304.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • William's Machine.Christopher J. Martin - 1986 - Journal of Philosophy 83 (10):564.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   23 citations  
  • Rewriting the History of Connexive Logic.Wolfgang Lenzen - 2022 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 51 (3):525-553.
    The “official” history of connexive logic was written in 2012 by Storrs McCall who argued that connexive logic was founded by ancient logicians like Aristotle, Chrysippus, and Boethius; that it was further developed by medieval logicians like Abelard, Kilwardby, and Paul of Venice; and that it was rediscovered in the 19th and twentieth century by Lewis Carroll, Hugh MacColl, Frank P. Ramsey, and Everett J. Nelson. From 1960 onwards, connexive logic was finally transformed into non-classical calculi which partly concur with (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • A Critical Examination of the Historical Origins of Connexive Logic.Wolfgang Lenzen - 2019 - History and Philosophy of Logic 41 (1):16-35.
    It is often assumed that Aristotle, Boethius, Chrysippus, and other ancient logicians advocated a connexive conception of implication according to which no proposition entails, or is entailed by, its own negation. Thus Aristotle claimed that the proposition ‘if B is not great, B itself is great […] is impossible’. Similarly, Boethius maintained that two implications of the type ‘If p then r’ and ‘If p then not-r’ are incompatible. Furthermore, Chrysippus proclaimed a conditional to be ‘sound when the contradictory of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • Aristotle's Use of Examples in the Prior Analytics.Katerina Ierodiakonou - 2002 - Phronesis 47 (2):127 - 152.
    This paper examines the relevance and importance of the large number of examples which Aristotle uses in his "Prior Analytics." In the first part of the paper three preliminary issues are raised: First, it investigates what counts as an example in Aristotle's syllogistic, and especially whether only examples expressed in concrete terms should be considered as examples or maybe also propositions and arguments with letters of the alphabet. The second issue concerns the kinds of examples Aristotle actually uses from everyday (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Strong Connexivity.Andreas Kapsner - 2012 - Thought: A Journal of Philosophy 1 (2):141-145.
    Connexive logics aim to capture important logical intuitions, intuitions that can be traced back to antiquity. However, the requirements that are imposed on connexive logic are actually not enough to do justice to these intuitions, as I will argue. I will suggest how these demands should be strengthened.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • Connexive Principles After a ‘Classical’ Turn in Medieval Logic.Spencer C. Johnston - 2021 - History and Philosophy of Logic 43 (3):251-263.
    The aim of this paper is to look at the arguments advanced by three Parisian arts masters about how to understand Prior Analytics II 4 and the more general discussion that medieval authors situate...
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Prior analytics.A. J. Jenkinson - 1984 - In Jonathan Barnes (ed.), Complete Works of Aristotle, Volume 1: The Revised Oxford Translation. Princeton University Press.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Aristotle's Use of Examples in the Prior Analytics.Katerina Ierodiakonou - 2002 - Phronesis 47 (2):127-152.
    This paper examines the relevance and importance of the large number of examples which Aristotle uses in his "Prior Analytics." In the first part of the paper three preliminary issues are raised: First, it investigates what counts as an example in Aristotle's syllogistic, and especially whether only examples expressed in concrete terms should be considered as examples or maybe also propositions and arguments with letters of the alphabet. The second issue concerns the kinds of examples Aristotle actually uses from everyday (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Aristotle on Conjunctive Propositions.P. T. Geach - 1963 - Ratio (Misc.) 5 (1):33.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Humble Connexivity.Andreas Kapsner - 2019 - Logic and Logical Philosophy 28.
    In this paper, I review the motivation of connexive and strongly connexive logics, and I investigate the question why it is so hard to achieve those properties in a logic with a well motivated semantic theory. My answer is that strong connexivity, and even just weak connexivity, is too stringent a requirement. I introduce the notion of humble connexivity, which in essence is the idea to restrict the connexive requirements to possible antecedents. I show that this restriction can be well (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations