Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. Kant, Hegel, and the Transcendental Material Conditions of Possible Experience.Kenneth R. Westphal - 1996 - Hegel Bulletin 17 (1):23-41.
    I argue that Hegel is aware of a crucial problem in Kant’s transcendental account of the conditions of human knowledge. Unless the matter of sensation is sufficiently ordered (and sufficiently varied) we could not make any cognitive judgments. In that case we could not distinguish ourselves from objects we know, and so could not be self-conscious. This is a necessary, formal and transcendental condition of possible human experience. However, it is also (as Kant acknowledged) a material – not a conceptual (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  • ‘Hegel on Political Representation: Laborers, Corporations, and the Monarch’.Kenneth R. Westphal - 1993 - The Owl of Minerva 25 (1):111-116.
    Hegel holds that members of a society can only be fully free and autonomous if they enjoy political representation. Hegel grants political representation to the landed aristocracy and to members of corporations. Causal day laborers fall outside both of these groups. Consequently, they lack political representation in Hegel’s state; hence they lack the political resources for full freedom and autonomy. This is a serious problem, but not so serious as Hegel’s marxist critics maintain. I propose two solutions based on Hegel’s (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Hegel’s Critique of Kant’s Moral World View.Kenneth R. Westphal - 1991 - Philosophical Topics 19 (2):133-176.
    Few if any of Kant’s critics were more trenchant than Hegel. Here I reconstruct some objections Hegel makes to Kant in a text that has received insufficient attention, the chapter titled ‘the Moral World View’ in the Phenomenology of Spirit. I show that Kant holds virtually all the tenets Hegel ascribes to ‘the moral world view’. I concentrate on five of Hegel’s main objections to Kant’s practical metaphysics. First, Kant’s problem of coordinating happiness with virtue (as worthiness to be happy) (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Kant and natural law ethics.J. B. Schneewind - 1993 - Ethics 104 (1):53-74.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • What Is Open and What Is Closed in the Philosophy of Hegel.David Kolb - 1991 - Philosophical Topics 19 (2):29-50.
    This essay studies the ways in which Hegel's thought demands "closure," critiques various proposals for an "open Hegelianism," and concludes that Hegel cannot achieve the closure he seeks, and that "open Hegelianisms" are not Hegelian because of their separations of form from content. Nonetheless the essay argues that Hegel can play an important role in the analyses of thought and culture today, in part as a corrective to excessive claims of openness and indeterminacy.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • The Permissive Law of Practical Reason in Kant's Metaphysics of Morals.Joachim Hruschka - 2004 - Law and Philosophy 23 (1):45-72.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • (1 other version)Hypothetical Consent in Kantian Constructivism.Thomas E. Hill - 2001 - Social Philosophy and Policy 18 (2):300-329.
    Epistemology, as I understand it, is a branch of philosophy especially concerned with general questions about how we can know various things or at least justify our beliefs about them. It questions what counts as evidence and what are reasonable sources of doubt. Traditionally, episte-mology focuses on pervasive and apparently basic assumptions covering a wide range of claims to knowledge or justified belief rather than very specific, practical puzzles. For example, traditional epistemologists ask “How do we know there are material (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • (2 other versions)Kant’s Transcendental Deduction as a Regressive Argument.Karl Ameriks - 1978 - Kant Studien 69 (1-4):273-287.
    Major recent interpretations of Kant's first "critique" (wolff, Strawson, Bennett) have taken his transcendental deduction to be an argument from the fact of consciousness to the existence of an objective world. I argue that it is unclear such an argument can succeed and there are overwhelming reasons to believe kant understood his deduction as having a very different form, namely as moving from the premise that there is empirical knowledge to the conclusion that there are universally valid pure categories. Detailed (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   36 citations  
  • We Can Act Only under the Idea of Freedom.Henry E. Allison - 1997 - Proceedings and Addresses of the American Philosophical Association 71 (2):39 - 50.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • How "Full" is Kant's Categorical Imperative?Kenneth Westphal - 1995 - Jahrbuch für Recht Und Ethik/Annual Review of Law and Ethics 3:465-509.
    Through a careful examination of two detailed investigations of Kant’s Categorical Imperative as a criterion for determining correct action I show that Hegel’s widely castigated critique of Kant’s CI has significant merit. Kant holds that moral imperatives are categorical because the obligations they express do not depend upon our contingent ends or desires and he holds that the CI is the supreme normative principle. However, his actual illustrations show that Kant repeatedly appeals to contingent ends and desires in deriving our (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Hegel's Standards of Political Legitimacy.Kenneth Westphal - 2002 - Jahrbuch für Recht Und Ethik/Annual Review of Law and Ethics 10:307-320.
    This critical review article on Frederick Neuhouser, The Foundations of Hegel’s Social Theory, examines in detail Hegel’s standards of political legitimacy, according to which social institutions are justified only by their roles in facilitating human freedom in its three basic forms: personal, moral, and social. Social freedom involves both ‘objective’ institutional requirements and ‘subjective’ aspects of personal understanding and endorsement of institutions so far as they fill their requirements. This includes rational, critical assessment of social institutions, and their role in (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • „Was erlaubt das Erlaubnisgesetz-und wozu braucht es Kant?“.Matthias Kaufmann - 2005 - Jahrbuch für Recht Und Ethik 13:195-219.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations