Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. The Forms in the Euthyphro and the Statesman: A Case against the Developmental Reading of Plato’s Dialogues.Michael Oliver Wiitala - 2014 - International Philosophical Quarterly 54 (4):393-410.
    The Euthyphro is generally considered one of Plato’s early dialogues. According to the developmental approach to reading the dialogues, when writing the Euthyphro Plato had not yet developed the sort of elaborate “theory of forms ” that we see presented in the middle dialogues and further refined in the late dialogues. This essay calls the developmental account into question by showing how key elements from the theory of forms that appear in the late dialogues, particularly in the Statesman, are already (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • (1 other version)Restless Forms and Changeless Causes.Fiona Leigh - 2012 - Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 112 (2pt2):239-261.
    It is widely held that in Plato's Sophist, Forms rest or change or both. The received opinion is, however, false—or so I will argue. There is no direct support for it in the text and several passages tell against it. I will further argue that, contrary to the view of some scholars, Plato did not in this dialogue advocate a kind of change recognizable as 'Cambridge change', as applicable to his Forms. The reason that Forms neither change nor rest is (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Textual notes on Plato's Sophist.David B. Robinson - 1999 - Classical Quarterly 49 (01):139-160.
    In editing Plato's Sophist for the new OCT vol. I, ed. E. A. Duke, W. F. Hicken, W. S. M. Nicoll, D. B. Robinson, and J. C. G. Strachan , there was less chance of giving novel information about W = Vind. Supp. Gr. 7 for this dialogue than for others in the volume, since Apelt's edition of 1897 was used by Burnet in 1900 and was based on Apelt's own collation of W. The result was better than the somewhat (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Speaking of Something: Plato’s Sophist and Plato’s Beard.Christine J. Thomas - 2008 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 38 (4):pp. 631-667.
    The Eleatic Visitor speaks forcefully when he insists, ‘Necessarily, whenever there is speech, it is speech of something; it is impossible for it not to be of something’. For ‘if it were not of anything, it would not be speech at all; for we showed that it is impossible for there to be speech that is speech of nothing’. Presumably, at 263c10, when he claims to have ‘shown’ that it is impossible for speech to be of nothing, the Visitor is (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • The ‘Holy Solemnity’ of Forms and the Platonic Interpretation of Sophist.Lloyd P. Gerson - 2006 - Ancient Philosophy 26 (2):291-304.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Plato's paradox that the immutable is unknowable.David Keyt - 1969 - Philosophical Quarterly 19 (74):1-14.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Motion and Rest as Genuinely Greatest Kinds in the Sophist.Christopher Buckels - 2015 - Ancient Philosophy 35 (2):317-327.
    The paper argues that Motion and Rest are “greatest kinds” and not just convenient examples, since they are all-pervading. Thus Motion and Rest can be jointly predicated of a single subject and can be predicated of each other, just as Sameness and Otherness can. While Sameness and Otherness are opposites, a single subject may be the same in one respect, namely, the same as itself, and other in another respect, namely, other than other things. Thus they can be predicated of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • The Relation of the Timaeus to Plato's Later Dialogues.Harold Cherniss - 1957 - American Journal of Philology 78 (3):225.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   26 citations  
  • Unity and Logos.Mitchell Miller - 1992 - Ancient Philosophy 12 (1):87-111.
    A close reading of Socrates’ arguments against the proposed definition of knowledge as true opinion together with a logos (“account”). I examine the orienting implications of his apparently destructive dilemma defeating the so-called dream theory and of his apparently decisive arguments rejecting the notions of “account” as verbalization, as working through the parts of the whole of the definiendum, and as identifying what differentiates the definiendum from all else. Whereas the dilemma implies of the object of knowledge that it must (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Platonic Causes.David Sedley - 1998 - Phronesis 43 (2):114-132.
    This paper examines Plato's ideas on cause-effect relations in the "Phaedo." It maintains that he sees causes as things (not events, states of affairs or the like), with any information as to how that thing brings about the effect relegated to a strictly secondary status. This is argued to make good sense, so long as we recognise that aition means the "thing responsible" and exploit legal analogies in order to understand what this amounts to. Furthermore, provided that we do not (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   66 citations  
  • The Motion of Intellect On the Neoplatonic Reading of Sophist 248e-249d.Eric D. Perl - 2014 - International Journal of the Platonic Tradition 8 (2):135-160.
    This paper defends Plotinus’ reading ofSophist248e-249d as an expression of the togetherness or unity-in-duality of intellect and intelligible being. Throughout the dialogues Plato consistently presents knowledge as a togetherness of knower and known, expressing this through the myth of recollection and through metaphors of grasping, eating, and sexual union. He indicates that an intelligible paradigm is in the thought that apprehends it, and regularly regards the forms not as extrinsic “objects” but as the contents of living intelligence. A meticulous reading (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • The Demiurge and the Forms.Eric D. Perl - 1998 - Ancient Philosophy 18 (1):81-92.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • (1 other version)Plato and Parmenides on the Timeless Present.G. E. L. Owen - 1966 - The Monist 50 (3):317-340.
    Some statements couched in the present tense have no reference to time. They are, if you like, grammatically tensed but logically tenseless. Mathematical statements such as ‘twice two is four’ or ‘there is a prime number between 125 and 128’ are of this sort. So is the statement I have just made. To ask in good faith whether there is still the prime number there used to be between 125 and 128 would be to show that one did not understand (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   29 citations  
  • Fast and Loose about Being.Dana Miller - 2004 - Ancient Philosophy 24 (2):339-363.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • (1 other version)X-R estless F orms and C hangeless C auses.Fiona Leigh - 2012 - Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 112 (2pt2):239-261.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Participation and Predication in Sophist 251-260.Richard J. Ketchum - 1978 - Phronesis 23:42.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations