Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. Why philosophy of art in cross-cultural perspective?Julius Moravcsik - 1993 - Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 51 (3):425-435.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Trying to define art as the sum of the arts.Stephen Davies - 2008 - Pazhouhesh Nameh-E Farhangestan-E Honar (Research Journal of the Iranian Academy of the Arts) 8:12–23.
    defining art conjunctively, that is, by defining the individual arts and joining these definitions in an exhaustive list. I suggest that the individual art forms are no easier to define than is the general category of art. As well, not everything falling within a given art form counts as art, not every instance of art in the given medium falls within the art form, and some artworks do not belong to an art form at all, so conjoining definitions of the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • The irreducible historicality of the concept of art.Jerrold Levinson - 2002 - British Journal of Aesthetics 42 (4):367-379.
    In this short paper I begin by underlining the sense in which my intentional-historical theory of art, first proposed in 1979, attributes to art a certain irreducible historicality. I next defend the theory, in broad outline, against a number of objections that have been raised against it in the past ten years. I conclude with some remarks on the similarities and differences between ordinary artefact concepts and the concept of an artwork.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  • (1 other version)Defining art historically.Jerrold Levinson - 1979 - British Journal of Aesthetics 19 (3):21-33.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   86 citations  
  • The cluster account of art defended.Berys Gaut - 2005 - British Journal of Aesthetics 45 (3):273-288.
    This paper replies to objections from Thomas Adajian, Stephen Davies, and Robert Stecker to my claim, defended in ‘"Art" as a Cluster Concept’, that ‘art’ is a cluster concept and so cannot be defined. The paper also clarifies and extends the arguments of the earlier paper and locates its position in relation to the work of Morris Weitz.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   31 citations  
  • A naturalist definition of art.Denis Dutton - 2006 - Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 64 (3):367–377.
    Aesthetic theoriesmayclaim universality, but they are normally conditioned by the aesthetic issues and debates of their own times. Plato and Aristo- tle were motivated both to account for the Greek arts of their day and to connect aesthetics to their general metaphysics and theories of value. Closer to our time, asNo¨el Carroll observes, the theories of Clive Bell and R.G. Collingwood can be viewed as “defenses of emerging avant-garde practices— neoimpressionism, on the one hand, and the mod- ernist poetics of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   22 citations  
  • The idealization of contingency in traditional japanese aesthetics.Robert Wicks - 2005 - Journal of Aesthetic Education 39 (3):88-101.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:The Idealization of Contingency in Traditional Japanese AestheticsRobert Wicks (bio)In many popular writings that date from the initial decades of the twentieth century, and also in recent scholarly studies, "Japanese aesthetics"—insofar as we can speak sweepingly of a complicated, multidimensional, and dynamic historical phenomenon—is characterized with a set of adjectives whose present linguistic entrenchment is clearly evident. Specifically we read that traditional Japanese aesthetics is an aesthetics of imperfection, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • The Myth of (Non-aesthetic) Artistic Value.Dominic McIver Lopes - 2011 - Philosophical Quarterly 61 (244):518-536.
    Art works realize many values. According to tradition, not all of these values are characteristic of art: art works characteristically bear aesthetic value. Breaking with tradition, some now say that art works bear artistic value, as distinct from aesthetic value. I argue that there is no characteristic artistic value distinct from aesthetic value. The argument for this thesis suggests a new way to think about aesthetic value as it is characteristically realized by works of art.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   27 citations  
  • (1 other version)Refining art historically.Jerrold Levinson - 1989 - Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 47 (1):21-33.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   57 citations  
  • Extending art historically.Jerrold Levinson - 1993 - Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 51 (3):411-423.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   31 citations  
  • The Story of Art.E. H. Gombrich - 1951 - Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 9 (4):339-340.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   62 citations  
  • (1 other version)The Art Instinct: Beauty, Pleasure, and Human Evolution.Mara Miller - 2009 - Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 67 (3):333-336.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   46 citations  
  • Definitions of Art.Eva Schaper - 1992 - Philosophical Quarterly 42 (167):259-260.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Definitions of Art.Ronald Moore - 1992 - Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 50 (2):155-157.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Defining Art and Artworlds.Stephen Davies - 2015 - Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 73 (4):375-384.
    Most art is made by people with a well-developed concept of art and who are familiar with its forms and genres as well as with the informal institutions of its presentation and reception. This is reflected in philosophers’ proposed definitions. The earliest artworks were made by people who lacked the concept and in a context that does not resemble the art traditions of established societies, however. An adequate definition must accommodate their efforts. The result is a complex, hybrid definition: something (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • Tea in Japan: Essays on the History of Chanoyu.Paul Varley & Kumakura Isao - 1990 - Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 48 (3):270.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Everyday Aesthetics.Yuriko Saito - 2007 - Oxford, GB: Oxford University Press.
    Everyday aesthetic experiences and concerns occupy a large part of our aesthetic life. However, because of their prevalence and mundane nature, we tend not to pay much attention to them, let alone examine their significance. Western aesthetic theories of the past few centuries also neglect everyday aesthetics because of their almost exclusive emphasis on art. In a ground-breaking new study, Yuriko Saito provides a detailed investigation into our everyday aesthetic experiences, and reveals how our everyday aesthetic tastes and judgments can (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   85 citations  
  • Everyday aesthetics.Yuriko Saito - 2001 - Philosophy and Literature 25 (1):87-95.
    Neglect of everyday aesthetics -- Significance of everyday aesthetics -- Aesthetics of distinctive characteristics and ambience -- Everyday aesthetic qualities and transience -- Moral-aesthetic judgments of artifacts.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   72 citations  
  • Aesthetics and the Philosophy of Art.Robert Stecker - 2006 - Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 64 (3):379-381.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • (1 other version)Non-Western Art and the Concept of Art: Can Cluster Theories of Art Account for the Universality of Art?Annelies Monseré - 2012 - Estetika: The European Journal of Aesthetics 49 (2):148-165.
    This essay seeks to demonstrate that there are no compelling reasons to exclude non-Western artefacts from the domain of art. Any theory of art must therefore account for the universality of the concept of art. It cannot simply start from ‘our’ art traditions and extend these conceptions to other cultures, since this would imply cultural appropriation, nor can it resolve the matter simply by formulating separate criteria for non-Western art, since this would imply that there is no unity in the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations