Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. An Introduction to the Principles of Morals and Legislation.Jeremy Bentham - 1780 - New York: Dover Publications. Edited by J. H. Burns & H. L. A. Hart.
    Bentham's best-known book stands as a classic of both philosophy and jurisprudence. The 1789 work articulates an important statement of the foundations of utilitarian philosophy — it also represents a pioneering study of crime and punishment. Bentham's reasoning remains central to contemporary debates in moral and political philosophy, economics, and legal theory.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   478 citations  
  • Hume on animals and morality.A. T. Nuyen - 1998 - Philosophical Papers 27 (2):93-106.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • John Gregory and the Invention of Professional Medical Ethics and the Profession of Medicine, and: John Gregory's Writings on Medical Ethics and Philosophy of Medicine, and: Medicine and Morals in the Enlightenment: John Gregory, Thomas Percival and Benjamin Rush (review).Heiner Klemme - 1999 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 37 (3):535-538.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Reviewed by:John Gregory and the Invention of Professional Medical Ethics and the Profession of Medicine by Laurence B. McCullough, John Gregory’s Writings on Medical Ethics and Philosophy of Medicine ed. by Laurence B. McCullough, Medicine and Morals in the Enlightenment: John Gregory, Thomas Percival and Benjamin Rush by Lisbeth HaakonssenHeiner F. KlemmeLaurence B. McCullough. John Gregory and the Invention of Professional Medical Ethics and the Profession of Medicine. Dordrecht, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • John Gregory and the Invention of Professional Medical Ethics and the Profession of Medicine, and: John Gregory's Writings on Medical Ethics and Philosophy of Medicine, and: Medicine and Morals in the Enlightenment: John Gregory, Thomas Percival and Benjamin Rush (review).Heiner Klemme - 1999 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 37 (3):535-538.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Reviewed by:John Gregory and the Invention of Professional Medical Ethics and the Profession of Medicine by Laurence B. McCullough, John Gregory’s Writings on Medical Ethics and Philosophy of Medicine ed. by Laurence B. McCullough, Medicine and Morals in the Enlightenment: John Gregory, Thomas Percival and Benjamin Rush by Lisbeth HaakonssenHeiner F. KlemmeLaurence B. McCullough. John Gregory and the Invention of Professional Medical Ethics and the Profession of Medicine. Dordrecht, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • John Gregory and the Invention of Professional Medical Ethics and the Profession of Medicine, and: John Gregory's Writings on Medical Ethics and Philosophy of Medicine, and: Medicine and Morals in the Enlightenment: John Gregory, Thomas Percival and Benjamin Rush (review).Heiner Klemme - 1999 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 37 (3):535-538.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Reviewed by:John Gregory and the Invention of Professional Medical Ethics and the Profession of Medicine by Laurence B. McCullough, John Gregory’s Writings on Medical Ethics and Philosophy of Medicine ed. by Laurence B. McCullough, Medicine and Morals in the Enlightenment: John Gregory, Thomas Percival and Benjamin Rush by Lisbeth HaakonssenHeiner F. KlemmeLaurence B. McCullough. John Gregory and the Invention of Professional Medical Ethics and the Profession of Medicine. Dordrecht, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • John Gregory and the Invention of Professional Medical Ethics and the Profession of Medicine, and: John Gregory's Writings on Medical Ethics and Philosophy of Medicine, and: Medicine and Morals in the Enlightenment: John Gregory, Thomas Percival and Benjamin Rush (review).Heiner Klemme - 1999 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 37 (3):535-538.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Reviewed by:John Gregory and the Invention of Professional Medical Ethics and the Profession of Medicine by Laurence B. McCullough, John Gregory’s Writings on Medical Ethics and Philosophy of Medicine ed. by Laurence B. McCullough, Medicine and Morals in the Enlightenment: John Gregory, Thomas Percival and Benjamin Rush by Lisbeth HaakonssenHeiner F. KlemmeLaurence B. McCullough. John Gregory and the Invention of Professional Medical Ethics and the Profession of Medicine. Dordrecht, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • The natural history of man in the Scottish Enlightenment.Paul B. Wood - 1990 - History of Science 28 (1):89-123.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   23 citations  
  • Hume on morals, animals, and men.Knut Erik Tranöy - 1959 - Journal of Philosophy 56 (3):94-103.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Descartes on the Moral Status of Animals.Gary Steiner - 1998 - Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie 80 (3):268-291.
    Conventional wisdom has long maintained that Descartes considered animals to be unfeeling machines with no capacity for perceptual states like pain, and that Descartes's mechanistic view of animals was the basis for his claim that we owe animals no moral obligations. Several recent commentators have sought to repudiate this conventional wisdom, either by denying that Descartes had a purely mechanistic conception of animal perception or by attempting to argue that Descartes allowed for the possibility that animals have souls. An examination (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Humanitarian attitudes in the early animal experiments of the royal society.Wallace Shugg - 1968 - Annals of Science 24 (3):227-238.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Hume and the Animals.Michael J. Seidler - 1977 - Southern Journal of Philosophy 15 (3):361-372.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • The Passions and Animal Language, 1540-1700.Richard Serjeantson - 2001 - Journal of the History of Ideas 62 (3):425-444.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Journal of the History of Ideas 62.3 (2001) 425-444 [Access article in PDF] The Passions and Animal Language, 1540-1700 R. W. Serjeantson "Do not think, kind and benevolent readers, that I am proposing a useless subject to you by choosing to discuss the language [loquela] of beasts. For this is nothing other than philosophy, which investigates the natures of animals." 1 The Italian medical professor Hieronymus Fabricius ab Aquapendente (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Hume on Morals and Animals.Tony Pitson - 2003 - British Journal for the History of Philosophy 11 (4):639 – 655.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • The Treatment of Animals.John Passmore - 1975 - Journal of the History of Ideas 36 (2):195.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Unmasking Descartes’s Case for the Bête Machine Doctrine.Lex Newman - 2001 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 31 (3):389-425.
    Among the more notorious of Cartesian doctrines is the bête machine doctrine – the view that brute animals lack not only reason, but any form of consciousness (having no mind or soul). Recent English commentaries have served to obscure, rather than to clarify, the historical Descartes' views. Standard interpretations have it that insofar as Descartes intends to establish the bête machine doctrine his arguments are palpably flawed. One camp of interpreters thus disputes that he even holds the doctrine. As I (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Unmasking Descartes’s Case for the Bête Machine Doctrine.Lex Newman - 2001 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 31 (3):389-425.
    Among the more notorious of Cartesian doctrines is thebête machinedoctrine — the view that brute animals lack not only reason, but any form of consciousness. Recent English commentaries have served to obscure, rather than to clarify, the historical Descartes's views. Standard interpretations have it that insofar as Descartes intends to establish thebête machinedoctrine his arguments are palpably flawed. One camp of interpreters thus disputes that he even holds the doctrine. As I shall attempt to show, not only does Descartes affirm (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Hume's influence on John Gregory and the history of medical ethics.Laurence B. McCullough - 1999 - Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 24 (4):376 – 395.
    The concept of medicine as a profession in the English-language literature of medical ethics is of recent vintage, invented by the Scottish physician and medical ethicist, John Gregory (1724-1773). Gregory wrote the first secular, philosophical, clinical, and feminine medical ethics and bioethics in the English language and did so on the basis of Hume's principle of sympathy. This paper provides a brief account of Gregory's invention and the role that Humean sympathy plays in that invention, with reference to key texts (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Descartes on animals.Peter Harrison - 1992 - Philosophical Quarterly 42 (167):219-227.
    Did Descartes deny that animals can feel? While it has generally been assumed that he did, there has been some confusion over the fact that Descartes concedes to animals both sensations and passions'. John Cottingham, for example, has argued that while Descartes did insist that animals were automata, denying them thought and "self"-consciousness, none of these assertions entail the conclusion that animals do not feel. This paper examines both Cottingham's arguments and the relevant sections of Descartes' writings, concluding that Descartes (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   29 citations  
  • Theriophily in Antiquity: A Supplementary Account.James E. Gill - 1969 - Journal of the History of Ideas 30 (3):401.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • From an introduction to the principles of morals and legislation.Jeremy Bentham - 1987 - In John Stuart Mill (ed.), Utilitarianism and Other Essays. Penguin Books.
    The following sheets were, as the note on the opposite page expresses, printed so long ago as the year 1780. The design, in pursuance of which they were written, was not so extensive as that announced by the present title. They had at that time no other destination than that of serving as an introduction to a plan of a penal code in terminus, designed to follow them, in the same volume.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   43 citations  
  • Hume on the Moral Difference between Humans and Other Animals.Denis G. Arnold - 1995 - History of Philosophy Quarterly 12 (3):303 - 316.
    The primary concern of this paper is Hume's account of the moral difference between humans and other animals. In order to clarify this difference Hume's views regarding reason, sympathy, and human sentiment are examined. The purpose of this investigation is threefold. First, Hume's position on the moral difference between humans and other animals is clarified. It is argued that this difference is properly traced to Hume's account of the sentiment of humanity. Second, Hume is defended against the claim that his (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Book reviews. [REVIEW]Heiner F. Klemme - 1999 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 37 (3):535.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • An Introduction to the Principles of Morals and Legislation.J. H. Burns, H. L. A. Hart & Jeremy Bentham - 1972 - Philosophy 47 (179):74-79.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   347 citations