Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. Immateriality and Separation in Avicenna and Thomas Aquinas.Pasquale Porro - 2011 - In Dag Nikolaus Hasse & Amos Bertolacci (eds.), The Arabic, Hebrew and Latin Reception of Avicenna's "Metaphysics". De Gruyter. pp. 275-308.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Aristotle's philosophy of mathematics.David Bostock - 2012 - In Christopher Shields (ed.), The Oxford Handbook of Aristotle. Oxford University Press USA. pp. 465.
    Much of Aristotle's thought developed in reaction to Plato's views, and this is certainly true of his philosophy of mathematics. To judge from his dialogue, the Meno, the first thing that struck Plato as an interesting and important feature of mathematics was its epistemology: in this subject we can apparently just “draw knowledge out of ourselves.” Aristotle certainly thinks that Plato was wrong to “separate” the objects of mathematics from the familiar objects that we experience in this world. His main (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Aristotle on Mathematical Truth.Phil Corkum - 2012 - British Journal for the History of Philosophy 20 (6):1057-1076.
    Both literalism, the view that mathematical objects simply exist in the empirical world, and fictionalism, the view that mathematical objects do not exist but are rather harmless fictions, have been both ascribed to Aristotle. The ascription of literalism to Aristotle, however, commits Aristotle to the unattractive view that mathematics studies but a small fragment of the physical world; and there is evidence that Aristotle would deny the literalist position that mathematical objects are perceivable. The ascription of fictionalism also faces a (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  • Notes on avicenna's concept of thingness (šay'iyya).Robert Wisnovsky - 2000 - Arabic Sciences and Philosophy 10 (2):181-221.
    Did classical kalām debates about how thing and existent relate to each other pave the way for Avicenna's distinction between essence and existence? There are some indications that the concept of thingness may have played a bridging role between the mutakallimūn's discussions and those of Avicenna. Nevertheless, Avicenna's appeals to thingness occur most densely in passages devoted to analyzing the relationship between efficient and final causes, an entirely Aristotelian topic. A philological question arises: should these passages be emended to read (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Imagination and estimation: Arabic paradigms and western transformations.Deborah L. Black - 2000 - Topoi 19 (1):59-75.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   24 citations  
  • (1 other version)Intelligence and the Philosophy of Mind.Jon McGinnis - 2006 - Proceedings of the American Catholic Philosophical Association 80:169-183.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Intentionality in Medieval Arabic Philosophy.Deborah L. Black - 2010 - Quaestio 10:65-81.
    It has long been a truism of the history of philosophy that intentionality is an invention of the medieval period, and within this standard narrative, the central place of Arabic philosophy has always been acknowledged. Yet there are many misconceptions surrounding the theories of intentionality advanced by the two main Arabic thinkers whose works were available to the West, Avicenna and Averroes. In the first part of this paper I offer an overview of the general accounts of intentionality and intentional (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • Estimation ( Wahm) in Avicenna: The Logical and Psychological Dimensions.Deborah L. Black - 1993 - Dialogue 32 (2):219-.
    One of the chief innovations in medieval adaptations of Aristotelian psychology was the expansion of Aristotle's notion of imagination orphantasiato include a variety of distinct perceptual powers known collectively as the internal senses. Amongst medieval philosophers in the Arabic world, Avicenna offers one of the most complex and sophisticated accounts of the internal senses. Within his list of internal senses, Avicenna includes a faculty known as “estimation”, to which various functions are assigned in a wide variety of contexts. Although many (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   35 citations  
  • Aristotle on Geometrical Objects.Ian Mueller - 1970 - Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie 52 (2):156-171.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   34 citations  
  • Summary of "Elements of Mind" and Replies to Critics.Tim Crane - 2004 - Croatian Journal of Philosophy 4 (11):223-240.
    Elements of Mind (EM) has two themes, one major and one minor. The major theme is intentionality, the mind’s direction upon its objects; the other is the mind–body problem. I treat these themes separately: chapters 1, and 3–5 are concerned with intentionality, while chapter 2 is about the mind–body problem. In this summary I will first describe my view of the mind–body problem, and then describe the book’s main theme. Like many philosophers, I see the mind–body problem as containing two (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   158 citations  
  • Aristotle’s Philosophy of Mathematics.Jonathan Lear - 1982 - Philosophical Review 91 (2):161-192.
    Whether aristotle wrote a work on mathematics as he did on physics is not known, and sources differ. this book attempts to present the main features of aristotle's philosophy of mathematics. methodologically, the presentation is based on aristotle's "posterior analytics", which discusses the nature of scientific knowledge and procedure. concerning aristotle's views on mathematics in particular, they are presented with the support of numerous references to his extant works. his criticism of his predecessors is added at the end.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   56 citations  
  • Aristotle's Philosophy of Mathematics.Constantine Cavarnos - 1953 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 14 (2):280-281.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Mathematics and the Mind: An Introduction Into Ibn Sīnā’s Theory of Knowledge.Hassan Tahiri - 2015 - Cham: Springer Verlag.
    Few philosophers that have been studied as much as Ibn Sīnā have been as much misunderstood. His extraordinary ability to reflect upon and write in a variety of styles about seemingly every topic in every domain has steered his thought from philosophy and theology to mysticism and esoterism. Instead of helping us to learn and understand better Ibn Sīnā than he has previously been understood, the recent surge of Avicennan studies only adds more confusion to the already complex social context (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Ibn Sina and Husserl on intention and intentionality.Marina Paola Banchetti-Robino - 2004 - Philosophy East and West 54 (1):71-82.
    : The concepts of intention and intentionality were particularly significant notions within the Christian, Jewish, and Islamic medieval philosophical traditions, and they regained philosophical importance in the twentieth century. The theories of intention and intentionality of the medieval Islamic philosopher and physician Ibn Sina and the phenomenological philosopher and mathematician Edmund Husserl are examined, compared, and contrasted here, showing that Ibn Sina's conception of intention is naturalistic and, in its naturalism, is influenced by the medical professional culture to which Ibn (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • A penetrating question in the history of ideas: Space, dimensionality and interpenetration in the thought of avicenna.Jon Mcginnis - 2006 - Arabic Sciences and Philosophy 16 (1):47-69.
    Avicenna's discussion of space is found in his comments on Aristotle's account of place. Aristotle identified four candidates for place: a body's matter, form, the occupied space, or the limits of the containing body, and opted for the last. Neoplatonic commentators argued contra Aristotle that a thing's place is the space it occupied. Space for these Neoplatonists is something possessing dimensions and distinct from any body that occupies it, even if never devoid of body. Avicenna argues that this Neoplatonic notion (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Mental Existence in Thomas Aquinas and Avicenna.Deborah L. Black - 1999 - Mediaeval Studies 61 (1):45-79.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  • The Metaphysical Location of Aristotle's "Mathematika".Michael White - 1993 - Phronesis 38:166.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Avicenna’s Theory of Supposition.Allan Bäck - 2013 - Vivarium 51 (1-4):81-115.
    Although he does not have an explicit theory of supposition as is found in the works of Latin medieval philosophers, Avicenna has two doctrines giving something equivalent: the threefold distinction of quiddity, corresponding to a division of simple, personal and material supposition, and his analyses of truth conditions for categorical propositions, where sentential context determines in part the reference of their terms. While he does address which individuals are being referred to by the universal terms used there, Avicenna concentrates more (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations