Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. An essay on rights.Hillel Steiner - 1994 - Oxford, UK ;: Blackwell.
    This book addresses the perennial question: What is justice?
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   173 citations  
  • What is it to wrong someone? A puzzle about justice.Michael Thompson - 2004 - In R. Jay Wallace (ed.), Reason and value: themes from the moral philosophy of Joseph Raz. New York: Oxford University Press. pp. 333-384.
    This will be the best way of explaining ‘Paris is the lover of Helen’, that is, ‘Paris loves, and by that very fact [et eo ipso] Helen is loved’. Here, therefore, two propositions have been brought together and abbreviated as one. Or, ‘Paris is a lover, and by that very fact Helen is a loved one’.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   96 citations  
  • What is it to Wrong Someone? A Puzzle about Justice.Michael Thompson - 2004 - In R. Jay Wallace (ed.), Reason and value: themes from the moral philosophy of Joseph Raz. New York: Oxford University Press.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   63 citations  
  • On human rights.James Griffin - 2008 - New York: Oxford University Press.
    It is our job now - the job of this book - to influence and develop the unsettled discourse of human rights so as to complete the incomplete idea.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   175 citations  
  • Why aren't duties rights&quest.Rowan Cruft - 2006 - Philosophical Quarterly 56 (223):175-192.
    I do not answer my title’s question in this paper. Instead, my aims are first to show that the question is worth asking, secondly to show that its answer will not be trivial, and thirdly to show that it is unclear what the answer is. From these three conclusions it follows that many contemporary Hohfeldian approaches to the conceptual analysis of rights (including those of Sumner, Jones, Kramer, Wenar and myself)1, while potentially capable of extensional accuracy, overlook an essential but (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Wrongs, Rights, and Third Parties.Nicolas Cornell - 2015 - Philosophy and Public Affairs 43 (2):109-143.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   24 citations  
  • Moral conflict and its structure.David O. Brink - 1994 - Philosophical Review 103 (2):215-247.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   80 citations  
  • The Moral Nexus.R. Jay Wallace - 2019 - Princeton: Princeton University Press.
    The Moral Nexus develops and defends a new interpretation of morality—namely, as a set of requirements that connect agents normatively to other persons in a nexus of moral relations. According to this relational interpretation, moral demands are directed to other individuals, who have claims that the agent comply with these demands. Interpersonal morality, so conceived, is the domain of what we owe to each other, insofar as we are each persons with equal moral standing. The book offers an interpretative argument (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   41 citations  
  • Prima Facie and Pro Tanto Oughts.Andrew Reisner - 2013 - In Hugh LaFollette (ed.), The International Encyclopedia of Ethics. Hoboken, NJ: Blackwell.
    There are many uses in English of the word “ought” (see Ought). This essay concerns the normative uses and the concepts or properties denoted thereby. In particular, it concerns two nonfinal oughts commonly used in the philosophical literature: prima facie oughts and pro tanto oughts.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • Making Exceptions.Barbara Herman - 2013 - In Stefano Bacin, Alfredo Ferrarin, Claudio La Rocca & Margit Ruffing (eds.), Kant und die Philosophie in weltbürgerlicher Absicht. Akten des XI. Internationalen Kant-Kongresses. Boston: de Gruyter. pp. 245-262.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Making Exceptions.Barbara Herman - 2013 - In Stefano Bacin, Alfredo Ferrarin, Claudio La Rocca & Margit Ruffing (eds.), Kant und die Philosophie in weltbürgerlicher Absicht. Akten des XI. Internationalen Kant-Kongresses. Boston: de Gruyter. pp. 245-262.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Rights and Demands: A Foundational Inquiry.Margaret Gilbert - 2018 - Oxford, United Kingdom: Oxford University Press.
    Margaret Gilbert presents the first full-length treatment of a central class of rights: demand-rights. To have such a right is to have the standing or authority to demand a particular action of another person. Gilbert argues that joint commitment is a ground of demand-rights, and gives joint commitment accounts of both agreements and promises.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   31 citations  
  • The theory of morality.Alan Donagan - 1977 - Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
    All this is tightly reasoned, the argument is packed, but the language is clear."—Christian Century "The man value of this book seems to me to be that it ...
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   97 citations  
  • The Nature of Claim-Rights.Leif Wenar - 2013 - Ethics 123 (2):202-229.
    This is a new analysis of rights, particularly of the paradigm: the claim-right. The new analysis makes better sense of rights than the leading alternatives do. The new analysis handles all of the well-known counterexamples to the Will and Interest theories; it seems not to generate counterexamples of its own; and it solves many long-standing puzzles in the theory of rights. Moreover, the central concepts of the new theory are as salient and forceful as are rights themselves.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   46 citations  
  • On Conflicts between Rights.Christopher Heath Wellman - 1995 - Law and Philosophy 14 (3/4):271 - 295.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • Rights in conflict.Jeremy Waldron - 1989 - Ethics 99 (3):503-519.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   50 citations  
  • Directed Duties and Inalienable Rights.Hillel Steiner - 2013 - Ethics 123 (2):230-244.
    This essay advances and defends two claims: (a) that rights cannot be inalienable and (b) that even if they could be, this would not be morally justifiable.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   26 citations  
  • Duties and their direction.Gopal Sreenivasan - 2010 - Ethics 120 (3):465-494.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   54 citations  
  • Reclaiming Proportionality.Arthur Ripstein - 2016 - Journal of Applied Philosophy 33 (3).
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Reclaiming Proportionality.Arthur Ripstein - 2016 - Journal of Applied Philosophy 34 (1):1-18.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • On the nature of rights.J. Raz - 1984 - Mind 93 (370):194-214.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   53 citations  
  • Are There Any Conflicts of Rights?Adina Preda - 2015 - Ethical Theory and Moral Practice 18 (4):677-690.
    This paper argues that a putative conflict between negative rights and positive rights is not a genuine conflict. The thought that they might conflict presupposes, I argue, that the two rights are valid. This is the first assumption of my argument. The second is that general rights impose duties on everyone, not just the party who faces a conflict of correlative duties. These two assumptions yield the conclusion that positive rights impose enforceable duties on the holder of the negative right; (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Specifying Rights Out of Necessity.John Oberdiek - 2008 - Oxford Journal of Legal Studies 28 (1):19.
    It is the purpose of this article to make the positive case for an under-appreciated conception of rights: specified rights. In contrast to rights conceived generally, a specified right can stand against different behaviour in different circumstances, so that what conflicts with a right in one context may not conflict with it in another. The specified conception of rights thus combines into a single inquiry the two questions that must be answered in invoking the general conception of rights, identifying the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   23 citations  
  • Lost in moral space: On the infringing/violating distinction and its place in the theory of rights.John Oberdiek - 2004 - Law and Philosophy 23 (4):325 - 346.
    The infringing/violating distinction, first drawn by Judith Jarvis Thomson, is central to much contemporary rights theory. According to Thomson, conduct that is in some sense opposed to a right infringes it, while conduct that is also wrong violates the right. This distinction finds a home what I call, borrowing Robert Nozick's parlance, a "moral space" conception of rights, for the infringing/violating distinction presupposes that, as Nozick puts it, "a line (or hyper-plane) circumscribes an area in moral space around an individual." (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Personal Rights and Public Space.Thomas Nagel - 1995 - Philosophy and Public Affairs 24 (2):83-107.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   68 citations  
  • When rights are permissibly infringed.Phillip Montague - 1988 - Philosophical Studies 53 (3):347 - 366.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • When rights conflict.Phillip Montague - 2001 - Legal Theory 7 (3):257-277.
    You and I are neighbors, with our houses situated closely together. You lead a group of rock musicians who can practice only in the evenings in your backyard; while I, on the other hand, enjoy nothing more than quiet evenings spent on my porch accompanied by the sounds of frogs and crickets. Presumably, you have a right to pursue your musical career, and I have a right quietly to enjoy my property. If we do indeed have these rights, however, then (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Directed Duties.Simon Căbulea May - 2015 - Philosophy Compass 10 (8):523-532.
    Directed duties are duties that an agent owes to some party – a party who would be wronged if the duty were violated. A ‘direction problem’ asks what it is about a duty in virtue of which it is directed towards one party, if any, rather than another. I discuss three theories of moral direction: control, demand and interest theories. Although none of these theories can be rejected out of hand, all three face serious difficulties.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   45 citations  
  • Conflicts of rights.F. M. Kamm - 2001 - Legal Theory 7 (3):239-255.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Being Helped and Being Grateful: Imperfect Duties, the Ethics of Possession, and the Unity of Morality.Barbara Herman - 2012 - Journal of Philosophy 109 (5-6):391-411.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • Scanlon on promissory obligation: The problem of promisees' rights.Margaret Gilbert - 2004 - Journal of Philosophy 101 (2):83 - 109.
    This article offers a critique of Thomas Scanlon's well-known account of promissory obligation by reference to the rights of promisees. Scanlon's account invokes a moral principle, the "principle of fidelity". Now, corresponding to a promisor's obligation to perform is a promisee's right to performance. It is argued that one cannot account for this right in terms of Scanlon's principle. This is so in spite of a clause in the principle relating to the promisee's "consent", which might have been thought to (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   32 citations  
  • Pro‐Tanto versus Absolute Rights.Danny Frederick - 2014 - Philosophical Forum 45 (4):375-394.
    Judith Jarvis Thomson and others contend that rights are pro-tanto rather than absolute, that is, that rights may permissibly be infringed in some circumstances. Alan Gewirth maintains that there are some rights that are absolute because infringing them would amount to unspeakable evil. However, there seem to be possible circumstances in which it would be permissible to infringe even those rights. Specificationists, such as Gerald Gaus, Russ Shafer-Landau, Hillel Steiner and Kit Wellman, argue that all rights are absolute because they (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  • Two men and a Plank.Claire Oakes Finkelstein - 2001 - Legal Theory 7 (3):279-306.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • The nature and value of rights.Joel Feinberg & Jan Narveson - 1970 - Journal of Value Inquiry 4 (4):243-260.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   256 citations  
  • Dimensions of Dignity: The Theory and Practice of Modern Constitutional Law.Jacob Weinrib - 2016 - Cambridge University Press.
    In an age of constitutional revolutions and reforms, theory and practice are moving in opposite directions. As a matter of constitutional practice, human dignity has emerged in jurisdictions around the world as the organizing idea of a groundbreaking paradigm. By reconfiguring constitutional norms, institutional structures and legal doctrines, this paradigm transforms human dignity from a mere moral claim into a legal norm that persons have standing to vindicate. As a matter of constitutional theory, however, human dignity remains an enigmatic idea. (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • The Idea of Private Law.Ernest Joseph Weinrib - 1995 - Oxford, United Kingdom: Oxford University Press UK.
    This revised edition of The Idea of Private Law makes one of the major works of modern legal theory accessible to a new generation of lawyers and students. It includes a new introduction by the author, looking back at the work, its origins, and its aspirations.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   30 citations  
  • Bi-polar obligation.Stephen Darwall - 2012 - Oxford Studies in Metaethics 7:333.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   50 citations  
  • British Ethical Theorists from Sidgwick to Ewing.Thomas Hurka - 2014 - Oxford: Oxford University Press.
    Thomas Hurka presents the first full historical study of an important strand in the development of modern moral philosophy. His subject is a series of British ethical theorists from the late nineteenth century to the mid-twentieth century, who shared key assumptions that made them a unified and distinctive school. The best-known of them are Henry Sidgwick, G. E. Moore, and W. D. Ross; others include Hastings Rashdall, H. A. Prichard, C. D. Broad, and A. C. Ewing. They disagreed on some (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   32 citations  
  • A Theory of Political Obligation: Membership, Commitment, and the Bonds of Society.Margaret Gilbert - 2006 - Oxford, GB: Oxford University Press.
    Does one have special obligations to support the political institutions of one’s own country precisely because it is one’s own? In short, does one have political obligations? This book argues for an affirmative answer, construing one’s country as a political society of which one is a member, and a political society as a special type of social group. The obligations in question are not moral requirements derived from general moral principles. They come, rather, from one’s participation in a special kind (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   119 citations  
  • Scanlon on Promissory Obligation.Margaret Gilbert - 2004 - Journal of Philosophy 101 (2):83-109.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   20 citations  
  • Self-Defense and Rights.Judith Jarvis Thomson - unknown
    This is the text of The Lindley Lecture for 1976, given by Judith Jarvis Thomson, an American philosopher.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   28 citations  
  • The Right and the Good.W. D. Ross - 1930 - International Journal of Ethics 41 (3):343-351.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   355 citations  
  • A Thinker-Based Approach to Freedom of Speech.Seana Valentine Shiffrin - 2011 - Constitutional Commentary 27 (2):283-307.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • The Theory of Morality.Alan Donagan - 1980 - Ethics 90 (2):301-305.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   64 citations  
  • The Right and the Good. By R. Robinson. [REVIEW]W. D. Ross - 1930 - International Journal of Ethics 41:343.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   393 citations  
  • The morality of freedom.J. Raz - 1988 - Revue Philosophique de la France Et de l'Etranger 178 (1):108-109.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   642 citations  
  • The Realm of Rights.J. J. Thomson - 1991 - Philosophy 66 (258):538-540.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   169 citations  
  • Review: Non-Consequentialism, the Person as an End-in-Itself, and the Significance of Status. [REVIEW]Frances Kamm - 1992 - Philosophy and Public Affairs 21 (4):354 - 389.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   59 citations  
  • The Right and the Good.W. D. Ross - 1932 - The Monist 42:157.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   277 citations  
  • The right and the good.W. Ross - 1932 - Revue de Métaphysique et de Morale 39 (2):11-12.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   385 citations