Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. An Ecological Theory of Rational Interpretation.Saku Hara - 2005 - Annals of the Japan Association for Philosophy of Science 13 (2):87-104.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Wittgenstein and the problem of consciousness.Oswald Hanfling - 2003 - Think 1 (3):99-106.
    You have a rich inner life of conscious experiences. For example, you have pains and other sensations. And you have sensory experiences, such as that produced by chewing on something bitter. Scientists are currently puzzling over how to explain this inner life in scientific terms. Can we, for example, consciousness by appealing to certain facts about our brains?
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Parallels between hearing and seeing support physicalism.Stephen Handel & Molly L. Erickson - 2003 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 26 (1):31-32.
    There are 2,000 hair cells in the cochlea, but only three cones in the retina. This disparity can be understood in terms of the differences between the physical characteristics of the auditory signal (discrete excitations and resonances requiring many narrowly tuned receptors) and those of the visual signal (smooth daylight excitations and reflectances requiring only a few broadly tuned receptors). We argue that this match supports the physicalism of color and timbre.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Neurophenomenology and the Spontaneity of Consciousness.Robert Hanna & Evan Thompson - 2003 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 33 (sup1):133-162.
    Consciousness is what makes the mind-body problem really intractable. My reading of the situation is that our inability to come up with an intelligible conception of the relation between mind and body is a sign of the inadequacy of our present concepts, and that some development is needed. Mind itself is a spatiotemporal pattern that molds the metastable dynamic patterns of the brain.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • The Brain Is Both Neurocomputer and Quantum Computer.Stuart R. Hameroff - 2007 - Cognitive Science 31 (6):1035-1045.
    _Figure 1. Dendrites and cell bodies of schematic neurons connected by dendritic-dendritic gap junctions form a laterally connected input_ _layer (“dendritic web”) within a neurocomputational architecture. Dendritic web dynamics are temporally coupled to gamma synchrony_ _EEG, and correspond with integration phases of “integrate and fire” cycles. Axonal firings provide input to, and output from, integration_ _phases (only one input, and three output axons are shown). Cell bodies/soma contain nuclei shown as black circles; microtubule networks_ _pervade the cytoplasm. According to the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  • From mimetic to mythic culture: Stimulus equivalence effects and prelinguistic cognition.P. J. Hampson - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (4):763-763.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Mythos and logos.John Halverson - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (4):762-762.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Do metamers matter?Martin Hahn - 2003 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 26 (1):30-31.
    Metamerism is a rather common feature of objects. The authors see it as problematic because they are concerned with a special case: metamerism in standard conditions. Such metamerism does not, however, pose a problem for color realists. There is an apparent problem in cases of metameric light sources, but to see such metamers as problematic is to fail to answer Berkeley's challenge.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • On relativity of time and the causal status of consciousness.Ali Habibi & Michael S. Bendele - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (2):404-405.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Husserlian Phenomenology as a Kind of Introspection.Christopher Gutland - 2018 - Frontiers in Psychology 9.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Know my own mind? I should be so lucky!Jennifer M. Gurd & John C. Marshall - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (1):47-48.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • On behalf of phenomenological parity for the attitudes.Keith Gunderson - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (1):46-47.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Dancing Chief in the Brain or Consciousness as an Entanglement.Yukio-Pegio Gunji & Kyoko Nakamura - 2020 - Foundations of Science 25 (1):151-184.
    Free will in intentional consciousness is exposed to skeptics since it was found that subconscious neural activities, what is called readiness potential, precedes the intention to an action. The question of whether free will is an authentic illusion has been argued not only in psychology but physics and philosophy. Most of scientists, however, think that the intentional consciousness who believes to have his/her own free will, is determined by readiness potential in advance, and that free will cannot coexist with determinism. (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Why do we need a computational theory of laboratory tasks?Robert L. Greene - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (4):668-669.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Nothing is instantaneous, even in sensation.Robert A. M. Gregson - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (2):210-211.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The historical basis of scientific discovery.Gerd Grasshoff - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (3):545-546.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The contents of consciousness: A neuropsychological conjecture.Jeffrey A. Gray - 1995 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 18 (4):659-76.
    Drawing on previous models of anxiety, intermediate memory, the positive symptoms of schizophrenia, and goal-directed behaviour, a neuropsychological hypothesis is proposed for the generation of the contents of consciousness. It is suggested that these correspond to the outputs of a comparator that, on a moment-by-moment basis, compares the current state of the organism's perceptual world with a predicted state. An outline is given of the information-processing functions of the comparator system and of the neural systems which mediate them. The hypothesis (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   41 citations  
  • Guilty consciousness.George Graham - 1995 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 18 (2):255-256.
    Should we distinguish between access and phenomenal consciousness? Block says yes and that various pathologies of consciousness support and clarify the distinction. The commentary charge that the distinction is neither supported nor clarified by the clinical data. It recommends an alternative reading of the data and urges Block to clarify the distinction.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Consciousness and its (dis)contents.Jeffrey A. Gray - 1995 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 18 (4):703-722.
    The first claim in the target article was that there is as yet no transparent, causal account of the relations between consciousness and brain-and-behaviour. That claim remains firm. The second claim was that the contents of consciousness consist, psychologically, of the outputs of a comparator system; the third consisted of a description of the brain mechanisms proposed to instantiate the comparator. In order to defend these claims against criticism, it has been necessary to clarify the distinction between consciousness-as-such and the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Anthropological criticisms of Dunbar's theory of the origin of language.Robert Bates Graber - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (4):705-705.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Setting the scientistic cat among the humanist pigeons.Andries Gouws - 2010 - South African Journal of Philosophy 29 (1):28-56.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Multivariant color vision.Peter Gouras - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (1):37-37.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Self-ascription of belief and desire.Robert M. Gordon - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (1):45-46.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Theories and illusions.Alison Gopnik - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (1):90-100.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Theories and qualities.Alison Gopnik - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (1):44-45.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • How we know our minds: The illusion of first-person knowledge of intentionality.Alison Gopnik - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (1):1-14.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   260 citations  
  • Strong and weak formal specifications.Richard M. Golden - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (4):668-668.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Functionalism, the theory-theory and phenomenology.Alvin I. Goldman - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (1):101-108.
    The ordinary understanding and ascription of mental states is a multiply complex subject. Widely discussed approaches to the subject, such as functionalism and the theory-theory (TT), have many variations and interpretations. No surprise, then, that there are misunderstandings and disagreements, which place many items on the agenda. Unfortunately, the multiplicity of issues raised by the commentators and the limitations of space make it impossible to give a full reply to everyone. My response is divided into five topics: (1) Which version(s) (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Competing accounts of belief-task performance.Alvin I. Goldman - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (1):43-44.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Are rules and instances subserved by separate systems?Robert L. Goldstone & John K. Kruschke - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (3):405-405.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • A cognitive theory without inductive learning.Lev Goldfarb - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (3):446-447.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Discovering the Principle of Finality in Computational Machines.Gonzalo Génova & Ignacio Quintanilla Navarro - 2018 - Foundations of Science 23 (4):779-794.
    In this essay we argue that the notion of machine necessarily includes its being designed for a purpose. Therefore, being a mechanical system is not enough for being a machine. Since the experimental scientific method excludes any consideration of finality on methodological grounds, it is then also insufficient to fully understand what machines are. Instead in order to understand a machine it is first required to understand its purpose, along with its structure, in clear parallel with Aristotle’s final and formal (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • The Hard Problem of Consciousness in the Light of Onto-Gnoseological Uncertainty.Ekaterina Nikolaevna Gnatik, Sergey Alexandrovich Lokhov, Dmitry Valerievich Mamchenkov & Maria Petrovna Matyushova - 2018 - Scientia et Fides 6 (2):101-113.
    Purpose: The main purpose of this article is to show that the paradigm of viewing the ‘hard problem’ of consciousness in analytic philosophy makes it a pseudo-problem rather than a ‘hard problem’. The objectives of this research included showing the reasons for the authors’ thesis, demonstrating the irreducibility of consciousness as a special layer of reality, and proposing a way to overcome these difficulties. Design/methodology/approach: In this article, the ‘hard problem’ of consciousness is viewed from the standpoints of the transcendental-phenomenological (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The Cartesian Theater stance.Bruce Glymour, Rick Grush, Valerie Gray Hardcastle, Brian Keeley, Joe Ramsey, Oron Shagrir & Ellen Watson - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (2):209-210.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Putting consciousness in a box: Once more around the track.Joseph Glicksohn - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (2):404-404.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • “Multiple Drafts” of subjective experience viewed within a microgenetic framework for cognition and consciousness.Joseph Glicksohn - 1995 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 18 (4):807-808.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Do gossip and lack of grooming make us human?Ilya I. Glezer & Warren G. Kinzey - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (4):704-705.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • On the adaptive advantage of always being right (even when one is not).Nathalia L. Gjersoe & Bruce M. Hood - 2009 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 32 (6):521-522.
    We propose another positive illusion that fits with McKay & Dennett's (M&D's) criteria for adaptive misbeliefs. This illusion is pervasive in adult reasoning but we focus on its prevalence in children's developing theories. It is a strongly held conviction arising from normal functioning of the doxastic system that confers adaptive advantage on the individual.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Working memory and its extensions.K. J. Gilhooly - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (4):761-762.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The Subjective Brain, Identity, and Neuroethics.Grant R. Gillett - 2009 - American Journal of Bioethics 9 (9):5-13.
    The human brain is subjective and reflects the life of a being-in-the-world-with-others whose identity reflects that complex engaged reality. Human subjectivity is shaped and in-formed (formed by inner processes) that are adapted to the human life-world and embody meaning and the relatedness of a human being. Questions of identity relate to this complex and dynamic reality to reflect the fact that biology, human ecology, culture, and one's historic-political situation are inscribed in one's neural network and have configured its architecture so (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  • Culture, the Crack’d Mirror, and the Neuroethics of Disease.Grant Gillett - 2016 - Cambridge Quarterly of Healthcare Ethics 25 (4):634-646.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Creativity theory: Detail and testability.K. J. Gilhooly - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (3):544-545.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Solving the language origins puzzle: Collecting and assembling all pertinent pieces.Kathleen R. Gibson - 1995 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 18 (1):189-190.
    Wilkins & Wakefield fall short of solving the language origin puzzle because they underestimate the cognitive and linguistic capacities of great apes. A focus on ape capacities leads to the recognition of varied levels of cognition and language and to a gradualistic model of language emergence in which early hominid language skills exceed those of the apes but fall far short of those of modern humans or later fossil hominid groups.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Performance-Similarity Reasoning as a Source for Mechanism Schema Evaluation.Raoul Gervais - 2020 - Topoi 39 (1):69-79.
    In this paper, I explicate and discuss performance-similarity reasoning as a strategy for mechanism schema evaluation, understood in Lindley Darden’s sense. This strategy involves inferring hypotheses about the mechanism responsible for cognitive capacities from premises describing the performance of those capacities; performance-similarity reasoning is a type of Inference to the Best Explanation, or IBE. Two types of such inferences are distinguished: one in which the performance of two systems is compared, and another when the performance of two systems under intervention (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Knowledge Argument: Scientific Reasoning and the Explanatory Gap.Rogério Gerspacher - 2018 - Axiomathes 28 (1):63-71.
    It is easy to accept that scientific reasoning cannot determine the characteristics of subjective experiences in cases like Broad’s archangel or Jackson’s Mary. The author questions why this seems to be evident and discusses the differences between these cases and ordinary scientific work, where future states of studied systems can be predicted in phenomenal terms. He concludes that important limitations of scientific reasoning are due to the inadequacy of human sensorial apparatus for representing physical reality. Such inadequacies were more evident (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • In Defense of H.O.T. Theory: A Second Reply to Adams and Shreve.Rocco J. Gennaro - 2017 - Symposion: Theoretical and Applied Inquiries in Philosophy and Social Sciences 4 (2):231-239.
    In Gennaro (2016), I had originally replied to Fred Adams and Charlotte Shreve’s (2016) paper entitled “What Can Synesthesia Teach Us About Higher Order Theories of Consciousness?,” previously published in Symposion. I argued that H.O.T. theory does have the resources to account for synesthesia and the specific worries that they advance in their paper, such as the relationship between concepts and experience and the ability to handle instances of ‘pop-out’ experiences. They counter-reply in Adams and Shreve (2017) and also raise (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Breaking continuous flash suppression: competing for consciousness on the pre-semantic battlefield.Surya Gayet, Stefan Van der Stigchel & Chris L. E. Paffen - 2014 - Frontiers in Psychology 5.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   23 citations  
  • Neurolímits.Òscar Llorens I. Garcia - 2018 - Recerca.Revista de Pensament I Anàlisi 22:15-32.
    Neuroscience promises us to explain philosophical issues, from ethics to general philosophy, as brain activity. I this paper we will propose expose the naturalistic view of neurophilosphy, show many problems of this proposal and how a dualistic ontology helps solve efficently these problems.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Art for art's sake.Alan Garnham - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (3):543-544.
    This piece is a commentary on a precis of Maggie Boden's book "The creative mind" published in Behavioral and Brain Sciences.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The measurement of consciousness: a framework for the scientific study of consciousness.David Gamez - 2014 - Frontiers in Psychology 5.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations