Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Making choices in anticipation of similar future choices can increase self-control.Kris N. Kirby & Barbarose Guastello - 2001 - Journal of Experimental Psychology: Applied 7 (2):154.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • Future directions for the melioration model of addiction.Kris N. Kirby - 1996 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 19 (4):583-583.
    For use in applied settings, the melioration model will need to incorporate changes in the shapes of local value functions over time, treat current value as a continuous function of time since previous choices, and take into account discounting of the effects of current behavior on future value. The policy implications of the model for regulating drugs are limited.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Habits, Self-Control and Social Conventions: The Role of Global Media and Corporations.Sae Won Kim & Chong Ju Choi - 2007 - Journal of Business Ethics 76 (2):147-154.
    There has been an intellectual debate at least since the 1960s in business ethics on the role of the media in relation to consumer choice driven by either habits or rationality. If consumers are totally rational, then the global media and global corporations provide just information and knowledge. If consumers are influenced by habit then large corporations and global media can greatly influence consumer choice and create problems of self-control (Ainslie, 1992, Pico Economics: The Strategic Interaction of Successive Motivational States (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Addiction: Taking the brain seriously.Steven E. Hyman - 1996 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 19 (4):582-582.
    Heyman's target article is an analytical tour de force, but it makes too hard a distinction between voluntary and driven behavior. It is more fruitful to think about brain and behavior as shifting, interacting “agents,” represented by multiple neural circuits. This has the virtue of better connecting behavioral analysis with wet neuroscience.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Melioration and addiction.Alasdair I. Houston - 1996 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 19 (4):581-582.
    I discuss various theoretical issues concerning maximizing, matching, and melioration. The model of addiction based on melioration has the key feature that a reduction in drag use increases both the value of drag-taking and the value of conventional activities. I found Heyman's target article stimulating. I don't feel competent to comment on drags but I do have some thoughts, both general and specific, on the theoretical issues.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Who determines the value of drug-taking behavior? Cultural considerations for a theory of behavioral choice.Riley E. Hinson - 1996 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 19 (4):580-581.
    Heyman's analysis of addiction suggests that drug taking is irrational. The irrationality of drug taking, however, may depend on the acceptance of mainstream society's view of what is valuable. Consideration of the addict's viewpoint and cultural aspects of drug taking may be useful in trying to fathom the “rationality” of drug taking.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Behavioral choice theory can enhance our understanding of drug dependence and other behavioral disorders.Stephen T. Higgins - 1996 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 19 (4):579-580.
    I support the major theme of Heyman's target article that behavioral choice theory can enhance our understanding of drug dependence, but I raise concerns about the critique of the operant model of drug dependence, the underscoring of melioration to the exclusion of other theories of choice, and assertions about the unique effects of drug reinforcement.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Which behavioral consequences matter? The importance of frame of reference in explaining addiction.Gene M. Heyman - 1996 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 19 (4):599-610.
    The target article emphasizes the relationship between a matching law-based theory of addiction and the disease model of addiction. In contrast, this response emphasizes the relationship between the matching law theory and other behavioral approaches to addiction. The basic difference, I argue, is that the matching law specifies that choice is governed by local reinforcement rates. In contrast, economics says that overall reinforcement rate controls choice, and for other approaches there are other measures or no clear prediction at all. The (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Resolving the contradictions of addiction.Gene M. Heyman - 1996 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 19 (4):561-574.
    Research findings on addiction are contradictory. According to biographical records and widely used diagnostic manuals, addicts use drugs compulsively, meaning that drug use is out of control and independent of its aversive consequences. This account is supported by studies that show significant heritabilities for alcoholism and other addictions and by laboratory experiments in which repeated administration of addictive drugs caused changes in neural substrates associated with reward. Epidemiological and experimental data, however, show that the consequences of drug consumption can significantly (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  • Book Review. [REVIEW]Francesco Guala - 2004 - Economics and Philosophy 20 (1):217-223.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Making room for options: Moral reasons, imperfect duties, and choice: Patricia Greenspan.Patricia Greenspan - 2010 - Social Philosophy and Policy 27 (2):181-205.
    An imperfect duty such as the duty to aid those in need is supposed to leave leeway for choice as to how to satisfy it, but if our reason for a certain way of satisfying it is our strongest, that leeway would seem to be eliminated. This paper defends a conception of practical reasons designed to preserve it, without slighting the binding force of moral requirements, though it allows us to discount certain moral reasons. Only reasons that offer criticism of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Setting the scientistic cat among the humanist pigeons.Andries Gouws - 2010 - South African Journal of Philosophy 29 (1):28-56.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Choice models and realistic ontologies: three challenges to neuro-psychological modellers.Roberto Fumagalli - 2016 - European Journal for Philosophy of Science 6 (1):145-164.
    Choice modellers are frequently criticized for failing to provide accurate representations of the neuro-psychological substrates of decisions. Several authors maintain that recent neuro-psychological findings enable choice modellers to overcome this alleged shortcoming. Some advocate a realistic interpretation of neuro-psychological models of choice, according to which these models posit sub-personal entities with specific neuro-psychological counterparts and characterize those entities accurately. In this article, I articulate and defend three complementary arguments to demonstrate that, contrary to emerging consensus, even the best available neuro-psychological (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Metacognitive Control of Categorial Neurobehavioral Decision Systems.Gordon R. Foxall - 2016 - Frontiers in Psychology 7.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • A scientific fix for the classical account of addiction.Jeffrey Foss - 1996 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 19 (4):579-579.
    Heyman's two crucial theses are that people over-value immediate rewards, and that addictive substances “subvert the value of competing commodities.” These perennial ideas were discussed by Plato. Whereas Heyman provides scientific clarification and support for the first, the second remains problematic. I outline how this deficiency might be remedied via evolutionary considerations.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The behavioral economics of addiction: A comprehensive alternative.Edmund Fantino - 1996 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 19 (4):578-579.
    Heyman's target article makes a strong case for a behavioral approach to addiction, yet some important assumptions require justification, and promising behavioral alternatives to the author's melioration approach should be considered. In particular, the behavioral economic approach to addiction appears well developed and comprehensive. How does the melioration approach complement or improve on a behavioral economic account?
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Decisions, Diachronic Autonomy, and the Division of Deliberative Labor.Luca Ferrero - 2010 - Philosophers' Imprint 10:1-23.
    It is often argued that future-directed decisions are effective at shaping our future conduct because they give rise, at the time of action, to a decisive reason to act as originally decided. In this paper, I argue that standard accounts of decision-based reasons are unsatisfactory. For they focus either on tie-breaking scenarios or cases of self-directed distal manipulation. I argue that future-directed decisions are better understood as tools for the non-manipulative, intrapersonal division of deliberative labor over time. A future-directed decision (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   32 citations  
  • Three Ways of Spilling Ink Tomorrow.Luca Ferrero - 2006 - In E. Baccarini & S. Prijic-Samarzija (eds.), Rationality in Belief and Action. Rijeka. pp. 95-127.
    There are three ways to control our future conduct: by causing it, by manipulating our future selves, or by taking future-directed decisions. I show that the standard accounts of future-directed decisions fail to do justice to their distinctive contribution in intentional diachronic agency. The standard accounts can be divided in two categories: First, those that conflate the operation of decisions with that of devices for either physical constraint or manipulative self-management. Second, accounts that, although they acknowledge the non-manipulative nature of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Craving the Right: Emotions and Moral Reasons.Patricia Greenspan - 2011 - In Carla Bagnoli (ed.), Morality and the Emotions. Oxford University Press. pp. 39.
    I first began working on emotions as a project in philosophy of action, without particular reference to moral philosophy. My thought was that emotions have a distinctive role to play in rationality that tends to be underappreciated by philosophers. Bringing this out was meant to counter a widespread tendency to treat emotions as “blind” causes of action (for the general picture, see Greenspan 2009.) Instead, I thought that emotions could be seen as providing reasons. I took their significance as moral (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Resting content: Sensible satisficing?Patricia Greenspan - 2009 - American Philosophical Quarterly 46 (4):305 - 317.
    Suppose I am now making plans for next summer’s vacation. I can spend a week in Rome or on the Riviera, but not both. Either choice would be excellent, but after weighing various pros and cons, I decide that for my purposes Rome would be better. If I am rational, then, I must choose Rome. It is an assumption of standard decision theory that rationality requires maximizing: trying to get the maximum amount of whatever form of value we are after (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations