Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. The Moral Value of Artistic Beauty in Kant.Joseph Cannon - 2011 - Kantian Review 16 (1):113-126.
    In the third Critique, Kant argues that it is to take an immediate interest in natural beauty, because it indicates an interest in harmony between nature and moral freedom. He, however, denies that there can be a similarly significant interest in artistic beauty. I argue that Kant ought not to deny this value to artistic beauty because his account of fine art as the joint product of the of genius and the discipline of taste commits him to the claim that (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Art and Science: A Philosophical Sketch of Their Historical Complexity and Codependence.Nicolas J. Bullot, William P. Seeley & Stephen Davies - 2017 - Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 75 (4):453-463.
    To analyze the relations between art and science, philosophers and historians have developed different lines of inquiry. A first type of inquiry considers how artistic and scientific practices have interacted over human history. Another project aims to determine the contributions that scientific research can make to our understanding of art, including the contributions that cognitive science can make to philosophical questions about the nature of art. We rely on contributions made to these projects in order to demonstrate that art and (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Mental imagery and the varieties of amodal perception.Robert Eamon Briscoe - 2011 - Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 92 (2):153-173.
    The problem of amodal perception is the problem of how we represent features of perceived objects that are occluded or otherwise hidden from us. Bence Nanay (2010) has recently proposed that we amodally perceive an object's occluded features by imaginatively projecting them into the relevant regions of visual egocentric space. In this paper, I argue that amodal perception is not a single, unitary capacity. Drawing appropriate distinctions reveals amodal perception to be characterized not only by mental imagery, as Nanay suggests, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   53 citations  
  • Raising the Mind to God: The Sensual Journey of Giovanni Morelli (1371–1444) via Devotional Images.Elizabeth Bailey - 2009 - Speculum 84 (4):984-1008.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Styled Morphogeometry.Liliana Albertazzi - 2020 - Axiomathes 30 (3):227-250.
    The paper presents analysis of form in different domains. It draws on the commonalities and their potential unified classifications based on how forms subjectively appear in perception—as opposed to their standard specification in Euclidean geometry or other objective quantitative methods. The paper provides an overview aiming to offer elements for thought for researchers in various fields.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Spatial Elements in Visual Awareness. Challenges for an Intrinsic “Geometry” of the Visible.Liliana Albertazzi - 2015 - Philosophia Scientiae 19:95-125.
    Un enjeu majeur pour les recherches actuelles dans les sciences de la vision consiste à mettre au point une approche dépendante de l’observateur – une science des apparences visuelles située au-delà de leur véridicité. L’espace dont nous faisons l’expérience subjective est en réalité hautement « illusoire», et les éléments de base du champ visuel sont des structures qualitatives, contextuelles et relationnelles, et non des indices métriques et dépendants du stimulus. Sur la base de nombreux résultats disponibles dans la littérature traitant (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Spatial Elements in Visual Awareness. Challenges for an Intrinsic “Geometry” of the Visible.Liliana Albertazzi - 2015 - Philosophia Scientiae 19:95-125.
    Un enjeu majeur pour les recherches actuelles dans les sciences de la vision consiste à mettre au point une approche dépendante de l’observateur – une science des apparences visuelles située au-delà de leur véridicité. L’espace dont nous faisons l’expérience subjective est en réalité hautement « illusoire», et les éléments de base du champ visuel sont des structures qualitatives, contextuelles et relationnelles, et non des indices métriques et dépendants du stimulus. Sur la base de nombreux résultats disponibles dans la littérature traitant (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Pictures, presence and visibility.Solveig Aasen - 2016 - Philosophical Studies 173 (1):187-203.
    This paper outlines a ‘perceptual account’ of depiction. It centrally contrasts with experiential accounts of depiction in that seeing something in a picture is understood as a visual experience of something present in the picture, rather than as a visual experience of something absent. The experience of a picture is in this respect akin to a veridical rather than hallucinatory perceptual experience on a perceptual account. Thus, the central selling-point of a perceptual account is that it allows taking at face (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Science and the Renaissance.William Persehouse Delisle Wightman - 1964 - History of Science 3 (1):1.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Foucault on painting.Catherine M. Soussloff - 2011 - History of the Human Sciences 24 (4):113-123.
    Michel Foucault’s understanding of painting oriented him and his readers to an alternative history of art through a means or an approach well known to philosophers and literary critics, that of irony. A close reading of the first chapter of The Order of Things shows that Foucault rejected the traditional interpretations of art history generated by a focus on the intentions of the individual artist, the identification of the subjects portrayed, and the expectations of a genre, relying instead on a (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Sammas ja labürint: Jüri Ehlvesti tekstuaalsest ruumist. Column and Labyrinth: On Jüri Ehlvest’s Textual Space.Virve Sarapik - 2009 - Methis: Studia Humaniora Estonica 3 (4).
    The purpose of this article is to analyze the connections of spatial relations and settings with narrative, and the presentation of these relations in Jüri Ehlvest’s texts. Distinctions are made between textual space (as designation, description, or rhetorical presentation) and fictional space (the space in which narrative action takes place and the site of the denouement of events). Fictional space can be expressed as textual space in one of the four following ways: (a) perceived space (b) experienced space (c) logical (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Capturing Shadows: On Photography, Causation, and Absences.Carl Mikael Pettersson - 2017 - Australasian Journal of Philosophy 95 (2):256-269.
    Many photographs seem to be images of absences: for instance, a photograph of a shadow seems to be an image of an absence, as shadows are plausibly thought of as being absences of light. Absence photography is puzzling, however, as, first, it is a common idea that photographs can only be images of things that have caused them, and, second, it is unclear whether absences can cause anything. In this paper, I look at various ways to unravel the puzzle. Along (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Capturing Shadows: On Photography, Causation, and Absences.Mikael Pettersson - 2017 - Australasian Journal of Philosophy 95 (2):256-269.
    Many photographs seem to be images of absences: for instance, a photograph of a shadow seems to be an image of an absence, as shadows are plausibly thought of as being absences of light. Absence photography is puzzling, however, as, first, it is a common idea that photographs can only be images of things that have caused them, and, second, it is unclear whether absences can cause anything. In this paper, I look at various ways to unravel the puzzle. Along (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Leonardo's constraint: two opaque objects cannot be seen in the same direction.Hiroshi Ono, Linda Lillakas, Philip M. Grove & Masahiro Suzuki - 2003 - Journal of Experimental Psychology: General 132 (2):253.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The Eroticism of Landscape in Contemporary Contemplative Cinema.Rosine Bénard O’Kelly - 2020 - Journal of Aesthetics and Phenomenology 7 (2):159-171.
    This article questions how contemplative contemporary cinema “sexualize” the landscapes. Through the filmography of four directors, Abbas Kiarostami, Apichatpong Weerasethakul, Lars von Trier and B...
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Painting and Philosophy.Michael Newall - 2014 - Philosophy Compass 9 (4):225-237.
    This article is primarily concerned with the philosophical problems that arise out of a consideration of painting. By painting I mean of course not any kind of application of paint to a surface – house painting for instance – but painting as an art, to use Richard Wollheim's phrase. Since Plato, philosophy has intermittently been concerned with these problems, and over the past 30 years, painting has come under a new focus as philosophy of art has increasingly turned its attention (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Franz Boas and the primacy of form.Bence Nanay - forthcoming - British Journal of Aesthetics:ayad029.
    There is systematic epistemic asymmetry between different centers of art production: we know far more about some (e.g. fifteenth-century Italian paintings) than about others (e.g. fifteenth-century Inca textiles). As long as we are focusing on the social context of the artworks or the artist’s intention, this epistemic asymmetry remains, given that we have vastly more information about the social context of the artworks or the artist’s intention when it comes to ‘Western’ art—again, because of the historically contingent differences in record-keeping (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • To Kirsti: ‘from Art History with Love…’ Perspective: Then and Now, and Artistic Practice.Marianne Marcussen - 2010 - Centaurus 52 (1):73-88.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • A Philosophical Path from Königsberg to Kyoto: The Science of the Infinite and the Philosophy of Nothingness.Rossella Lupacchini - 2020 - Sophia 60 (4):851-868.
    ‘Mathematics is the science of the infinite, its goal the symbolic comprehension of the infinite with human, that is finite, means.’ Along this line, in The Open World, Hermann Weyl contrasted the desire to make the infinite accessible through finite processes, which underlies any theoretical investigation of reality, with the intuitive feeling for the infinite ‘peculiar to the Orient,’ which remains ‘indifferent to the concrete manifold of reality.’ But a critical analysis may acknowledge a valuable dialectical opposition. Struggling to spell (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Informationalisation and culture: The mass media as transnational communities.Timothy W. Luke - 1995 - History of European Ideas 20 (4-6):873-881.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Elemental Optics: Nicholas of Cusa, Omnivoyance and the Aquatic Gaze.Taylor Knight - 2020 - Sophia 60 (4):819-849.
    There has been much recent debate about the nature of the omnivoyant image that introduces Nicholas of Cusa’s De visione Dei. In this paper, I argue that Cusa’s concept of contraction and his ‘radical perspectivism’ lead us toward stretching the concept of omnivoyance beyond a simple dichotomy between a phenomenology of the image and a phenomenology of the icon. Instead of putting such emphasis on what is seen by the omnivoyant, we should think an omnivoyant optics starting from the material (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Projection, Recognition, and Pictorial Diversity.Andrew Inkpin - 2015 - Theoria 82 (1):32-55.
    This article focuses on the difficulty for a general theory of depiction of providing a notion of pictorial content that accommodates the full diversity of picture types. The article begins by introducing two basic models of pictorial content using paradigmatic positions that maximize the ability of the respective models to deal with pictorial diversity. Kulvicki's On Images is interpreted as a generalized projection-based model which proposes a scene-centred notion of pictorial content. By contrast, Lopes's aspect-recognition theory, in Understanding Pictures, is (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Words and Pictures.John Hyman - 1997 - Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement 42:51-.
    Pictures have always played a prominent role in philosophical speculation about the mind, but the concept of a picture has itself been the object of philosophical scrutiny only intermittently. As a matter of fact, it was studied most intensively in the course of a theological controversy in the Eastern Roman Empire, during the eighth century - which is a sufficient indication of its marginal place in the history of philosophy. Perhaps this is because pictures have never produced in us the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Burckhardt and the ideology of the past.Michael Ann Holly - 1988 - History of the Human Sciences 1 (1):47-73.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The Primacy of Form over Color: On the Discussion of Primary and Secondary Qualities in Herder’s Pygmalion.Lasse Hodne - forthcoming - Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism.
    A key question in the art debate in the eighteenth and nineteenth centuries was whether color should be used for sculpture. Recent archaeological research had shown that the sculpture in ancient Greece was polychrome, but skepticism about applying paint to one’s own work was widespread among modern sculptors. Some scholars explain this reluctance as a consequence of racial prejudice: the Greek athlete was an image of white Europeans. This article will try to show that a re-reading of Johann Gottfried Herder’s (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Seventy-Five Years of Kant … and Counting.Paul Guyer - 2017 - Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 75 (4):351-362.
    There have been more articles on Kant's aesthetics in the history of the Journal than on the next four leading figures in the history of aesthetics combined. I argue that this is because Kant's aesthetic theory consists of multiple levels of theory that makes it accessible to and important for multiple approaches to the subject itself. Continuing issues for both Kant interpretation and for aesthetics in general arise at each of these levels, including the plausibility of the claim to universal (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Kant’s Theory of Modern Art?Paul Guyer - 2021 - Kantian Review 26 (4):619-634.
    Can Kant’s theory of fine art serve as a theory of modern art? It all depends on what ‘modern’ means. The word can mean current or contemporary, indexed to the time of use, and in that sense the answer is yes: Kant’s theory of genius implies that successful art is always to some extent novel, so there should always be something that counts as contemporary art on his theory. But ‘modern’ can also be used adjectively, perhaps more properly as ‘modernist’, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Beyond Resemblance.Gabriel Greenberg - 2013 - Philosophical Review 122 (2):215-287.
    What is it for a picture to depict a scene? The most orthodox philosophical theory of pictorial representation holds that depiction is grounded in resemblance. A picture represents a scene in virtue of being similar to that scene in certain ways. This essay presents evidence against this claim: curvilinear perspective is one common style of depiction in which successful pictorial representation depends as much on a picture's systematic differences with the scene depicted as on the similarities; it cannot be analyzed (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   43 citations  
  • Art as a product of nature as a work of art.Paul Feyerabend - 1994 - World Futures 40 (1):87-100.
    Two claims are discussed. One is that works of art are a product of nature, no less than rocks and flowers. The other is that nature itself is an artifact, constructed by scientists and artisans, throughout centuries, from a partly yielding, partly resisting material of unknown properties. Since both claims are supported by convincing evidence, the world appears much more slippery than commonly assumed by rationalists. Intellectual generalizations around ?art,? ?nature? or ?science? are simplifying devices that can help us order (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • What Is a Parergon?Paul Duro - 2019 - Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 77 (1):23-33.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Film space as mental space.Silvana Dunat - 2015 - Semiotica 2015 (207):475-487.
    Name der Zeitschrift: Semiotica Jahrgang: 2015 Heft: 207 Seiten: 475-487.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The Ends of Reason: Towards an Understanding of the Architectonic.Michael C. Duddy - 2018 - Journal of Aesthetics and Phenomenology 5 (1):1-13.
    In the Critique of Pure Reason, Kant defines the architectonic as the “art of constructing systems.” For him, architectonics is the systematic unity of knowledge according to a principle he identifies as the ends of reason. In the discipline of architecture, the concept of the architectonic has varied understandings: the unity of form of the appearance of the building that is given; or the order of the unity of form that systematizes the appearance as it is grasped; or the principle (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Immersive ideals / critical distances : study of the affinity between artistic ideologies in virtual Reality and previous immersive idioms.Joseph Nechvatal (ed.) - 2010 - Berlin: LAP Lambert Academic Publishing AG & Co KG.
    My research into Virtual Reality technology and its central property of immersion has indicated that immersion in Virtual Reality (VR) electronic systems is a significant key to the understanding of contemporary culture as well as considerable aspects of previous culture as detected in the histories of philosophy and the visual arts. The fundamental change in aesthetic perception engendered by immersion, a perception which is connected to the ideal of total-immersion in virtual space, identifies certain shifts in ontology which are relevant (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark