Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Classification from a computable viewpoint.Wesley Calvert & Julia F. Knight - 2006 - Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 12 (2):191-218.
    Classification is an important goal in many branches of mathematics. The idea is to describe the members of some class of mathematical objects, up to isomorphism or other important equivalence, in terms of relatively simple invariants. Where this is impossible, it is useful to have concrete results saying so. In model theory and descriptive set theory, there is a large body of work showing that certain classes of mathematical structures admit classification while others do not. In the present paper, we (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Notions of relative ubiquity for invariant sets of relational structures.Paul Bankston & Wim Ruitenburg - 1990 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 55 (3):948-986.
    Given a finite lexicon L of relational symbols and equality, one may view the collection of all L-structures on the set of natural numbers ω as a space in several different ways. We consider it as: (i) the space of outcomes of certain infinite two-person games; (ii) a compact metric space; and (iii) a probability measure space. For each of these viewpoints, we can give a notion of relative ubiquity, or largeness, for invariant sets of structures on ω. For example, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Scott complexity of countable structures.Rachael Alvir, Noam Greenberg, Matthew Harrison-Trainor & Dan Turetsky - 2021 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 86 (4):1706-1720.
    We define the Scott complexity of a countable structure to be the least complexity of a Scott sentence for that structure. This is a finer notion of complexity than Scott rank: it distinguishes between whether the simplest Scott sentence is $\Sigma _{\alpha }$, $\Pi _{\alpha }$, or $\mathrm {d-}\Sigma _{\alpha }$. We give a complete classification of the possible Scott complexities, including an example of a structure whose simplest Scott sentence is $\Sigma _{\lambda + 1}$ for $\lambda $ a limit (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Borel equivalence relations and classifications of countable models.Greg Hjorth & Alexander S. Kechris - 1996 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 82 (3):221-272.
    Using the theory of Borel equivalence relations we analyze the isomorphism relation on the countable models of a theory and develop a framework for measuring the complexity of possible complete invariants for isomorphism.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   23 citations  
  • An introduction to the Scott complexity of countable structures and a survey of recent results.Matthew Harrison-Trainor - 2022 - Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 28 (1):71-103.
    Every countable structure has a sentence of the infinitary logic $\mathcal {L}_{\omega _1 \omega }$ which characterizes that structure up to isomorphism among countable structures. Such a sentence is called a Scott sentence, and can be thought of as a description of the structure. The least complexity of a Scott sentence for a structure can be thought of as a measurement of the complexity of describing the structure. We begin with an introduction to the area, with short and simple proofs (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Countable structures, Ehrenfeucht strategies, and wadge reductions.Tom Linton - 1991 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 56 (4):1325-1348.
    For countable structures U and B, let $\mathfrak{U}\overset{\alpha}{\rightarrow}\mathfrak{B}$ abbreviate the statement that every Σ0 α (Lω1,ω) sentence true in U also holds in B. One can define a back and forth game between the structures U and B that determines whether $\mathfrak{U}\overset{\alpha}{\rightarrow}\mathfrak{B}$ . We verify that if θ is an Lω,ω sentence that is not equivalent to any Lω,ω Σ0 n sentence, then there are countably infinite models U and B such that $\mathfrak{U} \vDash \theta, \mathfrak{B} \vDash \neg \theta$ , (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The complexity of Scott sentences of scattered linear orders.Rachael Alvir & Dino Rossegger - 2020 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 85 (3):1079-1101.
    We calculate the complexity of Scott sentences of scattered linear orders. Given a countable scattered linear order L of Hausdorff rank $\alpha $ we show that it has a ${d\text {-}\Sigma _{2\alpha +1}}$ Scott sentence. It follows from results of Ash [2] that for every countable $\alpha $ there is a linear order whose optimal Scott sentence has this complexity. Therefore, our bounds are tight. We furthermore show that every Hausdorff rank 1 linear order has an optimal ${\Pi ^{\mathrm {c}}_{3}}$ (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations