Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. The Phenomenology of Adolf Reinach: Chapters in the Theory of Knowledge and Legal Philosophy.Lucinda Ann Vandervort Brettler - 1973 - Dissertation, Mcgill University (Canada)
    This dissertation engages in a critical analysis of the work of Adolf Reinach in the theory of knowledge and legal philosophy. Reinach had trained as a lawyer and brought that perspective and experience to bear in his phenomenological work on problems in evidence and legal philosophy. His contributions to phenomenology in the early 20th century provide a window into the earliest phases of the development of the phenomenological movement, prior to World War I. This dissertation locates this work in the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Ubicación espacial, exhortación y cuerpo: la espacialidad corporal del existir «entre las cosas circundantes».Felipe Johnson - 2024 - Pensamiento 79 (306):1739-1759.
    El presente artículo propone indagar el problema de nuestra ubicación espacial en términos existenciales. Para ello atenderemos a las consideraciones del espacio planteadas en la analítica del Dasein de Martin Heidegger, destacando un carácter de concernimiento según el cual el existir se despliega en cuanto relación ocupada con el mundo. Atendiendo a las descripciones de Oskar Becker, se planteará la pregunta si acaso una inclusión del fenómeno del cuerpo puede contribuir a una comprensión de nuestro particular «hallarnos en un lugar». (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • (2 other versions)Adolf Reinach: An annotated bibliography.Barry Smith - 1987 - In Kevin Mulligan (ed.), Speech Act and Sachverhalt: Reinach and the Foundations of Realist Phenomenology. Reidel. pp. 299-332.
    Ever since its appearance in 1913, Reinach's work on a The A Priori Foundations of the Civil Law has served as the principal representative of phenomenological, aprioristic and ontological/realist approaches to the philosophy of law. This annotated bibliography provides an overview of the reception of Reinach's thinking, which has been of influence also in the realm of speech act theory.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • La physique naïve: un essai d'ontologie.Barry Smith & Roberto Casati - 1993 - Intellectica 17 (2):173--197.
    The project of a naive physics has been the subject of attention in recent years above all in the artificial intelligence field, in connection with work on common-sense reasoning, perceptual representation and robotics. The idea of a theory of the common-sense world is however much older than this, having its roots not least in the work of phenomenologists and Gestalt psychologists such as Kohler, Husserl, Schapp and Gibson. This paper seeks to show how contemporary naive physicists can profit from a (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Thomas Ryckman: The reign of relativity. Philosophy in physics 1915–1925. [REVIEW]Mark van Atten - 2008 - Husserl Studies 24 (1):73-78.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • ¿Cómo pensar el cuerpo al margen de la idea de sujeto corporal? ‘Mera presencia’ y ‘claro del ser’ en ‘Zollikoner Seminare’ de Heidegger.Felipe Johnson - 2020 - Anales Del Seminario de Historia de la Filosofía 37 (1):85-98.
    . Este artículo se propone discutir las dificultades que pertenecen al ejercicio de pensarnos en cuanto corporales. Guía de estas reflexiones son los índices heideggerianos sobre la corporalidad humana realizados en Zollikoner Seminare. Dichos seminarios advierten que la actual experiencia de nuestro cuerpo, pese a poder ser estimada como inmediata, se halla mediada por nuestros propios supuestos epocales y se enraiza ya en el pensar ontológico de Occidente. Así, este artículo intentará examinar las aporías filosóficas de tal mediación histórico-epocal, exponiendo (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • "Entre las cosas cotidianas": El aparecer del mundo sensible desde la fenomenologia temprana.Felipe Johnson - 2018 - Trans/Form/Ação 41 (1):163-190.
    Este artículo se propone describir el modo de aparecimiento del mundo sensible, entendiéndolo como el primer suelo sobre el cual la vida humana se instala efectivamente entre cosas concretas. Se intentará desvincular este nivel de presencia inmediata y cotidiana del mundo exterior del modo como tradicionalmente se le concibe, a saber, en el sentido de una manifestación “objetual”. En este contexto, se recurrirá a descripciones fenomenológicas de la percepción que tuvieron lugar principalmente en trabajos filosóficos y psicológicos de la primera (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Erich Kretschmann as a proto-logical-empiricist: Adventures and misadventures of the point-coincidence argument.Marco Giovanelli - 2013 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part B: Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics 44 (2):115-134.
    The present paper attempts to show that a 1915 article by Erich Kretschmann must be credited not only for being the source of Einstein’s point-coincidence remark, but also for having anticipated the main lines of the logical-empiricist interpretation of general relativity. Whereas Kretschmann was inspired by the work of Mach and Poincaré, Einstein inserted Kretschmann’s point-coincidence parlance into the context of Ricci and Levi-Civita’s absolute differential calculus. Kretschmann himself realized this and turned the point-coincidence argument against Einstein in his second (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Becker–Blaschke problem of space.Julien Bernard - 2015 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part B: Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics 52 (Part B):251-266.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Objective Time and the Experience of Time: Husserl’s Theory of Time in Light of Some Theses of A. Einstein’s Special Theory of Relativity.Pedro M. S. Alves - 2008 - Husserl Studies 24 (3):205-229.
    In this paper, I start with the opposition between the Husserlian project of a phenomenology of the experience of time, started in 1905, and the mathematical and physical theory of time as it comes out of Einstein’s special theory of relativity in the same year. Although the contrast between the two approaches is apparent, my aim is to show that the original program of Husserl’s time theory is the constitution of an objective time and a time of the world, starting (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Questions regarding Husserlian geometry and phenomenology. A study of the concept of manifold and spatial perception.Luciano Boi - 2004 - Husserl Studies 20 (3):207-267.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Review. [REVIEW]Andreas Kamlah - 1986 - Erkenntnis 24 (2):235-252.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Is Husserl’s Antinaturalism up to Date? A Critical Review of the Contemporary Attempts to Mathematize Phenomenology.Andrij Wachtel - 2022 - Husserl Studies 38 (2):129-150.
    Since the end of the last century, there has been several ambitious attempts to naturalize Husserlian phenomenology by way of mathematization. To justify themselves in view of Husserl’s adamant antinaturalism, many of these attempts appeal to the new physico-mathematical tools that were unknown in Husserl’s time and thus allegedly make his position outdated. This paper critically addresses these mathematization proposals and aims to show that Husserl had, in fact, sufficiently good arguments that make his antinaturalistic position sound even today. The (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Thomas Ryckman: The Reign of Relativity. Philosophy in Physics 1915–1925. [REVIEW]Mark Atten - 2008 - Husserl Studies 24 (1):73-78.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Brouwer, as never read by Husserl.Mark van Atten - 2003 - Synthese 137 (1-2):3-19.
    Even though Husserl and Brouwer have never discussed each other's work, ideas from Husserl have been used to justify Brouwer's intuitionistic logic. I claim that a Husserlian reading of Brouwer can also serve to justify the existence of choice sequences as objects of pure mathematics. An outline of such a reading is given, and some objections are discussed.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • (1 other version)Free variation and the intuition of geometric essences: Some reflections on phenomenology and modern geometry.Richard Tieszen - 2005 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 70 (1):153–173.
    Edmund Husserl has argued that we can intuit essences and, moreover, that it is possible to formulate a method for intuiting essences. Husserl calls this method 'ideation'. In this paper I bring a fresh perspective to bear on these claims by illustrating them in connection with some examples from modern pure geometry. I follow Husserl in describing geometric essences as invariants through different types of free variations and I then link this to the mapping out of geometric invariants in modern (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  • Searches for the origins of the epistemological concept of model in mathematics.Gert Schubring - 2017 - Archive for History of Exact Sciences 71 (3):245-278.
    When did the concept of model begin to be used in mathematics? This question appears at first somewhat surprising since “model” is such a standard term now in the discourse on mathematics and “modelling” such a standard activity that it seems to be well established since long. The paper shows that the term— in the intended epistemological meaning—emerged rather recently and tries to reveal in which mathematical contexts it became established. The paper discusses various layers of argumentations and reflections in (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • The Geometry of Knowledge: Lewis, Becker, Carnap and the Formalization of Philosophy in the 1920s.Alan Richardson - 2003 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 34 (1):165-182.
    On an ordinary view of the relation of philosophy of science to science, science serves only as a topic for philosophical reflection, reflection that proceeds by its own methods and according to its own standards. This ordinary view suggests a way of writing a global history of philosophy of science that finds substantially the same philosophical projects being pursued across widely divergent scientific eras. While not denying that this view is of some use regarding certain themes of and particular time (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Phänomenologie der Zeit und der Zeitlichkeit bei Husserl und Heidegger.Günther Neumann - 2023 - Heidegger Studies 39 (1):149-208.
    Phenomenology of Time and Temporality in Husserl and Heidegger Since objective time cannot be presupposed in phenomenology, the question of the constitution and nature of time represents a central task of every phenomenological analysis. The purpose of this contribution is to offer a comparison of the phenomenological analyses of time and temporality in Edmund Husserl and Martin Heidegger and thereby to set out the fundamental differences of their approaches. In addition to the foundational lectures and texts On the Phenomenology of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Geometry, intuition and experience: From Kant to Husserl. [REVIEW]Ulrich Majer - 1995 - Erkenntnis 42 (2):261 - 285.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Kant’s hands, spatial orientation, and the Copernican turn.Peter Woelert - 2007 - Continental Philosophy Review 40 (2):139-150.
    In this paper we want to show how far the early, pre-critical Kant develops a theory of the constitution of space that not only anticipates insights usually attributed to the phenomenological theory of lived space with its emphasis on the constitutively central role of the human lived-body, but which also establishes the foundation for Kant’s Copernican turn according to which space is understood as ‘form of intuition’, implied in the activity of the transcendental subject. The key to understand this role (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Otto Selz’s phenomenology of natural space.Klaus Robering - 2020 - Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences 19 (1):97-121.
    In the 1930s Otto Selz developed a novel approach to the psychology of perception which he called “synthetic psychology of wholes”. This “synthetic psychology” is based on a phenomenological description of the structural relationships between elementary items building up integral wholes. The present article deals with Selz’s account of spatial cognition within this general framework. Selz Zeitschrift für Psychologie, 114, 351–362 argues that his approach to spatial cognition delivers answers to the long-discussed question of the epistemological status of the laws (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Carnap and Weyl on the foundations of geometry and relativity theory.Michael Friedman - 1995 - Erkenntnis 42 (2):247-260.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • (1 other version)Collision of Traditions. The Emergence of Logical Empiricism Between the Riemannian and Helmholtzian Traditions.Marco Giovanelli - 2013 - .
    This paper attempts to explain the emergence of the logical empiricist philosophy of space and time as a collision of mathematical traditions. The historical development of the ``Riemannian'' and ``Helmholtzian'' traditions in 19th century mathematics is investigated. Whereas Helmholtz's insistence on rigid bodies in geometry was developed group theoretically by Lie and philosophically by Poincaré, Riemann's Habilitationsvotrag triggered Christoffel's and Lipschitz's work on quadratic differential forms, paving the way to Ricci's absolute differential calculus. The transition from special to general relativity (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark